The tenure game. The tenure game. Winning strategies for the tenure game. Winning condition for the tenure game

Similar documents
Game Theory and Randomized Algorithms

Notes for Recitation 3

Tutorial 1. (ii) There are finite many possible positions. (iii) The players take turns to make moves.

2. The Extensive Form of a Game

Topic 1: defining games and strategies. SF2972: Game theory. Not allowed: Extensive form game: formal definition

NORMAL FORM GAMES: invariance and refinements DYNAMIC GAMES: extensive form

Tilings with T and Skew Tetrominoes

1.6 Congruence Modulo m

Sequential games. Moty Katzman. November 14, 2017

12. 6 jokes are minimal.

Generalized Game Trees

Chapter 1. Probability

Analyzing Games: Solutions

Contents. MA 327/ECO 327 Introduction to Game Theory Fall 2017 Notes. 1 Wednesday, August Friday, August Monday, August 28 6

TROMPING GAMES: TILING WITH TROMINOES. Saúl A. Blanco 1 Department of Mathematics, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY 14853, USA

On the Periodicity of Graph Games

ON SPLITTING UP PILES OF STONES

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 19: Nim & Impartial Combinatorial Games

Senior Math Circles February 10, 2010 Game Theory II

18 Completeness and Compactness of First-Order Tableaux

TOPOLOGY, LIMITS OF COMPLEX NUMBERS. Contents 1. Topology and limits of complex numbers 1

The next several lectures will be concerned with probability theory. We will aim to make sense of statements such as the following:

3432 IEEE TRANSACTIONS ON INFORMATION THEORY, VOL. 53, NO. 10, OCTOBER 2007

Permutation Groups. Definition and Notation

To be able to determine the quadratic character of an arbitrary number mod p (p an odd prime), we. The first (and most delicate) case concerns 2

ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE (CS 370D)

STAJSIC, DAVORIN, M.A. Combinatorial Game Theory (2010) Directed by Dr. Clifford Smyth. pp.40

Constructions of Coverings of the Integers: Exploring an Erdős Problem

arxiv: v1 [cs.dm] 13 Feb 2015

1. The chance of getting a flush in a 5-card poker hand is about 2 in 1000.

Permutation Groups. Every permutation can be written as a product of disjoint cycles. This factorization is unique up to the order of the factors.

Extensive Games with Perfect Information. Start by restricting attention to games without simultaneous moves and without nature (no randomness).

Math 1313 Section 6.2 Definition of Probability

3 Game Theory II: Sequential-Move and Repeated Games

Multiplayer Pushdown Games. Anil Seth IIT Kanpur

Solutions for the Practice Final

From a Ball Game to Incompleteness

Section Summary. Finite Probability Probabilities of Complements and Unions of Events Probabilistic Reasoning

18.204: CHIP FIRING GAMES

arxiv: v2 [cs.cc] 18 Mar 2013

BMT 2018 Combinatorics Test Solutions March 18, 2018

Mohammad Hossein Manshaei 1394

Lesson 11.3 Independent Events

Pure strategy Nash equilibria in non-zero sum colonel Blotto games

Week 1. 1 What Is Combinatorics?

Chapter 1. Probability

SF2972: Game theory. Mark Voorneveld, February 2, 2015

Axiomatic Probability

Dynamic Games: Backward Induction and Subgame Perfection

Two-person symmetric whist

CIS 2033 Lecture 6, Spring 2017

Yale University Department of Computer Science


Advanced Automata Theory 4 Games

SOLUTIONS FOR PROBLEM SET 4

The topic for the third and final major portion of the course is Probability. We will aim to make sense of statements such as the following:

Peeking at partizan misère quotients

Game Theory two-person, zero-sum games

Principle of Inclusion-Exclusion Notes

1. Introduction to Game Theory

Computational aspects of two-player zero-sum games Course notes for Computational Game Theory Section 3 Fall 2010

Cutting a Pie Is Not a Piece of Cake

On Range of Skill. Thomas Dueholm Hansen and Peter Bro Miltersen and Troels Bjerre Sørensen Department of Computer Science University of Aarhus

Some Unusual Applications of Math

DVA325 Formal Languages, Automata and Models of Computation (FABER)

Extensive Form Games: Backward Induction and Imperfect Information Games

What is counting? (how many ways of doing things) how many possible ways to choose 4 people from 10?

37 Game Theory. Bebe b1 b2 b3. a Abe a a A Two-Person Zero-Sum Game

Combinatorics and Intuitive Probability

Formal Verification. Lecture 5: Computation Tree Logic (CTL)

NIM Games: Handout 1

Extensive Games with Perfect Information A Mini Tutorial

The Product Rule can be viewed as counting the number of elements in the Cartesian product of the finite sets

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2016 Rao and Walrand Note 13

A theorem on the cores of partitions

GEOMETRIC DISTRIBUTION

Lecture 5: Subgame Perfect Equilibrium. November 1, 2006

Probability MAT230. Fall Discrete Mathematics. MAT230 (Discrete Math) Probability Fall / 37

GEOGRAPHY PLAYED ON AN N-CYCLE TIMES A 4-CYCLE

VARIATIONS ON NARROW DOTS-AND-BOXES AND DOTS-AND-TRIANGLES

Edge-disjoint tree representation of three tree degree sequences

PUTNAM PROBLEMS FINITE MATHEMATICS, COMBINATORICS

Game Theory, Alive. Yuval Peres with contributions by David B. Wilson. September 27, Check for updates at

18.S34 (FALL, 2007) PROBLEMS ON PROBABILITY

COMP 2804 solutions Assignment 4

Combinatorial Game Theory: An Introduction to Tree Topplers

The extensive form representation of a game

Combined Games. Block, Alexander Huang, Boao. icamp Summer Research Program University of California, Irvine Irvine, CA

The Chinese Remainder Theorem

Game Theory and an Exploration of 3 x n Chomp! Boards. Senior Mathematics Project. Emily Bergman

Experiments on Alternatives to Minimax

Goldbach Conjecture (7 th june 1742)

Math 152: Applicable Mathematics and Computing

Adversary Search. Ref: Chapter 5

Strategic Bargaining. This is page 1 Printer: Opaq

MATHEMATICS 152, FALL 2004 METHODS OF DISCRETE MATHEMATICS Outline #10 (Sets and Probability)

3-2 Lecture 3: January Repeated Games A repeated game is a standard game which isplayed repeatedly. The utility of each player is the sum of

23 Applications of Probability to Combinatorics

Applied Statistics I

Section II.9. Orbits, Cycles, and the Alternating Groups

Transcription:

The tenure game The tenure game is played by two players Alice and Bob. Initially, finitely many tokens are placed at positions that are nonzero natural numbers. Then Alice and Bob alternate in their moves where always first Bob partitions the tokens in two parts, then Alice chooses one part that is removed, while the other tokens move one position closer to position 0. Bob wins if and only if some token reaches position 0. Picture each token as a nontenured staff member who gets tenure at position 0; Alice is head of department and wants to prevent staff from getting tenure, whereas Bob is dean and wants to give tenure to as many people as possible. The tenure game Initial configuration of the tenure game. Finitely many tokens,..., m are placed at positions d,..., d m where the d i are arbitrary nonzero natural numbers. The moves in the tenure game. I Partition. Bob partitions the current set I of tokens that are not at position 0 into two sets I 0 and I (i.e., I is the disjoint union of I 0 and I ). II Selection. Alice determines a bit r. III Removal and promotion. The tokens in I r are removed. The tokens in I r are moved on step closer to position 0 Tokens that were already at position 0 just stay there. Winning condition for the tenure game Winning strategies for the tenure game Termination of the tenure game. The tenure game ends when each token either has been removed or has reached position 0. Winning condition for the tenure game. Bob wins if some token reaches position 0, otherwise, Alice wins. Observe that a tenure game is decided and hence may be stopped as soon as some token has reached position 0 because then the token will stay at position 0 and Bob will win. However, the version of the game where the play goes on until the termination condition holds is equivalent and somewhat easier to analyze. For any given initial configuration of the tenure game, either Alice or Bob has a winning strategy. The observation holds because the tenure game is a finite two-person zero-sum game with complete information, see the excursus on such games at the end of this section. Question Given an initial configuration of the tenure game, who has a winning strategy, Alice or Bob?

Games that Alice win and games that Bob win Examples of initial configurations for the tenure game. (i) 2 k - tokens at position k. (ii) 2 k tokens at position k. (iii) One token at each position through k. (iv) One token at each position through k and two tokens at position k. (v) Two tokens at each position 2 through k. (vi) Two tokens at each position 2 through k and four tokens at position k. It is not so hard to see that the odd-numbered configurations are winning for Alice and the other configurations are winning for Bob. A randomized strategy for Alice Alice determines each bit r by tossing of a fair coin. No matter what the strategy of Bob is and how Bob partitions, when Alice plays the randomized strategy, then each time Alice selects, any single token will be removed or promoted with equal probabilities of /2. Furthermore, since the coin tosses are independent, a token that is initially at position d, will reach position 0 with probabilty /2 d. Question What is the general pattern? Consider the tenure game where initially tokens,..., m are placed at positions d,..., d m, respectively. Fix any strategy for Bob. Assume Alice plays the randomized strategy. Define indicator variables X,..., X m where X i is if and only if token i reaches position 0. Let X = X +... + X m be the number of tokens that reach the origin. The expectation of X is E [X ] = E [X + +X m ] = E [X ]+ +E [X m ] = 2 d + + 2. dm For any configuration with m tokens at positions d,..., d m, we call d 2dm the potential of the configuration. Consider a tenure game where the potential d 2 the intial configuration is strictly less than. In this situation, also E [X ], the expected number of tokens that reach position 0, is strictly less than Hence there must be some sequence of coin tosses where X <, i.e., such that no token reaches position 0. dm of This means that there is a sequence of coin tosses such that Alice wins. The argument above does not depend on Bob s strategy. That is, no matter what the strategy of Bob is, Alice can win. As a consequence, Bob cannot have a winning strategy. But then Alice must have a winning strategy.

Winning strategy for Alice Proposition If the potential of the initial configuration is strictly less than, then Alice has a winning strategy. How does the winning strategy according to the proposition look like? A terminal configuration is a configuration where all tokens are at position 0. The potential of a terminal configuration is equal to the number of its tokens A terminal configuration is winning for Alice if and only if the potential of the configuration is strictly less than. Idea for a strategy: Alice tries to maintain the invariant that the potential of the current situation is strictly less than. Winning strategy for Alice If the initial configuration has potential strictly less than, then Alice can maintain this property by the following strategy. Strategy for Alice Choose r such that when comparing the potentials of the two configurations that correspond to I 0 and I, the potential that corresponds to I r is higher. Assume that no token has yet reached position 0, and consider the partition of the set I of current tokens into I 0 and I. If we let p, p 0, and p be equal to the potentials that correspond to I, I 0 and I, respectively, we have p = p 0 + p. After the tokens in I r have been promoted, the potential of the new configuration is 2p r. By choice of r we have 2p r p 0 + p = p. Winning strategy for Bob What s about initial configurations with potential of or more? A terminal configuration is winning for Bob if and only if the potential of the configuration is at least. Bob wins if he can maintain the invariant that the potential is at least. Suppose Bob partitions the set of current tokens into sets I 0 and I where both correspond to a potential of at least /2. Then the subsequent promotion step ensures that the potential will be at least again. Strategy for Bob Partition the set of current tokens into sets I 0 and I such that both sets correspond to a potential of at least /2. Bob can partition equally By the following lemma, the strategy for Bob is feasible. Lemma Let d... d m be a nondecreasing sequence of nonzero natural numbers where d 2 dm 2. Then there is an index t such that 2 d + + = 2 dt 2. Proof. By assumption on the d i, let t be minimum such that s t = d 2 d t 2. In case s t = /2 we are done. Otherwise, s t and /2 are both multiples of but differ by 2 d t less than 2, a contradiction. d t

In a finite two-person game with perfect information two players alternate in specifying moves, the player whose turn it is to specify the next move knows the sequence of previous moves, there are always at most finitely many possible moves, any admissible sequence of games ends after a finite number of steps with one player winning and the other player losing. The situation reached in such a game after a certain sequence of moves is called a configuration. Configurations can be assumed to be finitely represented because in any case one can specify a configuration by the sequence of moves that led to the configuration. The game tree of a finite two-person game with perfect information is a labeled tree where each node is labeled with a configuration of the game, the root of the tree is labeled with the initial configuration, the children of a node are labeled in a one-to-one fashion with the configurations that can be reached by an admissible move from the this nodes configurations. Game trees of finite two-person games with perfect information are always finite. The observation is an immediate consequence of König s Lemma. König s Lemma Any finitely branching infinite tree has an infinite path. Proof. Let T be any finitely branching infinite tree. We construct inductively an infinite path v 0, v,... on T. As an invariant of the construction, any node on the path is chosen such that the subtree of T below this node is infinite. Initially, let v 0 be equal to the root of T. In the induction step, given the already constructed initial segment v 0,... v i, let v i+ be equal to the least such child of v i such that the subtree below this child is infinite. Such a child exists because the subtree of T below v i is infinite and v i has only finitely many children. Furthermore, the invariant is always true, hence the construction will not terminate and yields an infinite path on T. Definition Consider a two-person game with players A and B. A strategy for Player A is a function that determines the next move of Player A whenever it is A s turn to specify a move. A winning strategy for Player A is a strategy such that Player A always wins when using this strategy, no matter what strategy Player B uses. Strategies and winning strategies for Player B are defined likewise in the obvious way. Definition A two-person game with perfect information is determined if one of the two players has a winning strategy.

Theorem Finite two-person games with perfect information are determined. Proof. Fix any finite two-person game with perfect information. We have already seen that the game tree T of this game is finite. We show for every node v of T that the subgame that starts at v is determined; we show this by induction on the height of the subtree of T with root v If the height of the subtree is 0, the node is a leave of the tree and one of the players wins immediately. In the induction step consider a node v where the subtree has height h > 0 and assume that at v Player A specifies a move. By the induction hypothesis, for all children of v the corresponding subgames are determined. In case A has a winning strategy for one of these subgames, then A has winning strategy from v; otherwise B has a winning strategy from v. Consider a two-person game with perfect information played by A and B. If A has a winning strategy, then A always wins when using this strategy, no matter what strategy B uses. If A has no winning strategy, this does not imply directly that B has a winning strategy, but only that for any strategy of A there is some strategy of B such that B will win. Remark Infinite two-person games with perfect information in general are not determined. Consider an infinite two-person game where two players alternate in specifying the next bit of an infinite sequence and A wins if and only if the resulting sequence is contained in a certain set C of sequences, otherwise B wins. Using the axiom of choice, one can show that there are certain sets C for which this game is not determined.