The Digital Challenge: Photographic Realism Revisited

Similar documents
Thirty-Minute Essay Questions from Earlier AP Exams

1. MacBride s description of reductionist theories of modality

HOW PHOTOGRAPHY HAS CHANGED THE IDEA OF VIEWING NATURE OBJECTIVELY. Name: Course. Professor s name. University name. City, State. Date of submission

3.3 Creative imagery through Photomontage

Art and Art History - Photography

The project was financed by the National Science Centre for the doctoral scholarship upon the decision no. DEC 2016/20/T/HS1/00470.

PRESS COVERAGE HIGHLIGHTS

WIMPing Out: Looking More Deeply at Digital Game Interfaces

Common Sense Assumptions About Intentional Representation in Student Artmaking and Exhibition in The Arts: Initial Advice Paper.

REINTERPRETING 56 OF FREGE'S THE FOUNDATIONS OF ARITHMETIC

Image source: Other source:

Term 3 Grade 6 Visual Arts

Technology and Normativity

The Necessity of Time in the Perception of Three Dimensions: A Preliminary Inquiry

Uploading and Consciousness by David Chalmers Excerpted from The Singularity: A Philosophical Analysis (2010)

#ARTS-110 COURSE SYLLABUS FOR PHOTOGRAPHY I. Michael DeRosa Instructor

ASSIGNMENT ONE: COLOR WHEELS AND TEMPLATES (5 pieces)

Intimation of life : photographic portraiture in art

The Rockwell Museum. Fifth Grade Tour: Environments of the American West: Earth, Air, Fire & Water. Pre and Post Visit Materials

Game Mechanics Minesweeper is a game in which the player must correctly deduce the positions of

NCEA Level Photography 2013

With the development of memory and thus the ability to extend consciousness over time, general awareness leads to

The Representation of the Visual World in Photography

Thesis Project - CS297 Fall David Robert Smith

ART 269 3D Animation The 12 Principles of Animation. 1. Squash and Stretch

Kubrick s Use of Composition in 2001: A Space Odyssey. Gabriel Nell / UC Berkeley

In the last chapter we took a close look at light

Hot or Cold? Warm Colors: Yellow, Orange, Red (excitement) Cool Colors: Green, Blue, Violet (calmness)

Types of Composition. 1) Open Composition

ECON 312: Games and Strategy 1. Industrial Organization Games and Strategy

Robert B.Hallock Draft revised April 11, 2006 finalpaper2.doc

High Dynamic Range (HDR) Photography in Photoshop CS2

Summer Art Assignments Handout Revised June 2018 Distributed in June prior to the AP year. AP Studio Art: An Overview

Vassilis S. Vassiliadis, Ph.D., Senior Lecturer,

SECTION I - CHAPTER 2 DIGITAL IMAGING PROCESSING CONCEPTS

Tropes and Facts. onathan Bennett (1988), following Zeno Vendler (1967), distinguishes between events and facts. Consider the indicative sentence

Digital Photography Assignment Portraiture

Source photo, sketchbook collage and digital collage

Summit Public Schools--Summit, New Jersey. Grade 8 Art Cycle. Length of Course: 45 Days. Curriculum

photoshop filters kelly ludwig assistant professor

as the Altgens6 shirtsleeve. On the Internet, the Altgens6 photo is pixelated, as are the FBI photos of Lovelady s and Oswald s shirts.

Raymond Klass Photography Newsletter

37 Game Theory. Bebe b1 b2 b3. a Abe a a A Two-Person Zero-Sum Game

XXXX - ILLUSTRATING FROM SKETCHES IN PHOTOSHOP 1 N/08/08

Art Journal 3 (SL) Joseph Sullivan

2. GENERAL CLARIFICATION OF INTRINSIC ELEMENTS IN LITERATURE. In this chapter, the writer will apply the definition and explanation about

Drawing Portfolio. Advanced Placement Studio Art. Drawing embodies a genuine and independent way of thinking. Phillip Rawson

Exemplar for Internal Achievement Standard. Visual Arts Level 3

A WORKING MODEL FOR DEMONSTRATING THE MOSAIC THEORY OF THE COMPOUND EYE

V5.02. Augmented Imagination: Machine Learning Art as Automatism. Philipp Schmitt

Year 8 Art Homework Booklet Term 1

Communication Engineering Prof. Surendra Prasad Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Delhi

Performativity and its implications for philosophy of science

In Response to Peg Jumping for Fun and Profit

MAS336 Computational Problem Solving. Problem 3: Eight Queens

The case for a 'deficit model' of science communication

Open Lab Hours: Will be posted on the studio door after the first week of classes. Taylor 008, 022

Terms and Conditions Trustpower Photographic Exhibition Competition

ADVANCED PLACEMENT STUDIO ART

TCSAAL Visual Art Rules

A Three Cycle View of Design Science Research

THE IN-VISIBLE, THE (IM)POSSIBILITY OF ITS REPRESENTATION AND ITS INTERPRETATION IN ARCHITECTURAL DRAWING

The Unique Role of Lucis Differential Hysteresis Processing (DHP) in Digital Image Enhancement

More Than A Pencil: Using the Computer to Make Two-Dimensional Art

B&W Photos from Colour:

Artist photo: Roshanak

Post Millennium Tension

Screening Basics Technology Report

Philpot & Philipson: Remote Sensing Fundamentals Color 6.1 W.D. Philpot, Cornell University, Fall 2012 W B = W (R + G) R = W (G + B)

Topic 6 - Optics Depth of Field and Circle Of Confusion

EMVA1288 compliant Interpolation Algorithm

A SPATIAL ILLUSION. Isometric Projection in the East

Composition in Photography

PROCESSING ERRORS and the DIGITAL FIX

Pearly White. An interview with Clive Head by Rosalyn Best

2. REVIEW OF RELATED LITERATURE

Fruity Fruit Veggy Veg

Adam Aziz 1203 Words. Artificial Intelligence vs. Human Intelligence

AP Language and Composition Grade 11 Summer Reading and Assignments

Awareness and Understanding in Computer Programs A Review of Shadows of the Mind by Roger Penrose

SECONDARY 1 EXP /NA /NT SCHEME OF WORK

INTERMEDIATE SCIENCE Grade 8

What is Social Realism?

Chess Beyond the Rules

ANALYZING LIGHT USING CATCHLIGHTS

Horace A picture is worth a thousand words. Napoleon Bonaparte A work of art is the unique result of a unique

A MOVING-KNIFE SOLUTION TO THE FOUR-PERSON ENVY-FREE CAKE-DIVISION PROBLEM

Cambridge English Proficiency Reading and Use of English: Part 7

Artist Member Jurying

4/9/2015. Simple Graphics and Image Processing. Simple Graphics. Overview of Turtle Graphics (continued) Overview of Turtle Graphics

Your texture pattern may be slightly different, but should now resemble the sample shown here to the right.

Impressionists Painting ( )

Lesson Plans Patron, Master Artist, and Apprentice: A Symbiotic Relationship Visual Arts Grades 6 12

WaterColors that. al vesselli.com. Painting Glass. Lesson 1. Contemporary Realism Techniques Using Watercolors

THE RELATIVE IMPORTANCE OF PICTORIAL AND NONPICTORIAL DISTANCE CUES FOR DRIVER VISION. Michael J. Flannagan Michael Sivak Julie K.

The popular conception of physics

Cutting a Pie Is Not a Piece of Cake

Splinters from the Keyboard Artistic Work and the Experience of Production

Realism, Impressionism, and Nineteenth-Century Photography. One of the most appropriate examples of the nineteenth-century photography

Communication Engineering Prof. Surendra Prasad Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Delhi

Transcription:

The Digital Challenge: Photographic Realism Revisited Geert Gooskens * University of Antwerp Abstract. It has been argued that digital photography, unlike its analog predecessor, is not realistic. The digital photograph would be more like a painting than like an analog photographs, as it can veraciously portray the world but does not inevitably do so. Plausible as this thesis might seem we are all familiar with the possibility to manipulate digital pictures I will argue against it. In my paper, I make a case for digital photography s realism, arguing that the strong causal link between picture and depictum, i.e. the link warranting analog photography s realism, is also present in digital photography. Photography is traditionally regarded as a particularly realistic type of depiction. Whereas a painting can depict a state of affairs, a photograph necessarily does so. Photography s strong realism has been the cornerstone of a wide range of theories about the medium. 1 Recently, however, these realistic theories have been challenged. Not by philosophical arguments, but by the arrival of a new technique for creating pictures of the world: digital photography. It has been argued that digital photographs lack the essential realism of their analog predecessors. 2 They would be more like paintings, as they can realistically depict the world but do not inevitably do so. Still, the thesis that digital photography is not realistic, plausible as it might seem, leads to a dilemma with two equally undesirable outcomes. Either the thesis implies that: (1) Realism is not an essential property of photography, as there are photographs digital ones which lack it. * Email: geert.gooskens@ua.ac.be 1 Walton (2008), Barthes (1982) 2 Mitchell (1992), Savedoff (1992) 115

This outcome is undesirable, since it leaves us without a criterion to distinguish photography from other (non-realistic) types of depiction, like painting. Or the thesis implies that: (2) Digital photographs are not photographs at all, as photographs are essentially realistic. This outcome is undesirable too, because it is so counterintuitive: we usually refer to pictures made with digital cameras as photographs. To avoid this unpleasant dilemma, I will argue that the thesis from which it originates that digital photography is not realistic is false. I make a case for digital photography s realism in three sections: First, I introduce the traditional definition of photographic realism, i.e. the one derived from analog photography (section 1). Next, I present two ways in which digital photography challenges and resists such a realistic understanding (section 2). Third, I take on these two digital challenges to argue that digital photography is just as realistic as its analog predecessor (section 3). 1. Two Kinds of Photographic Realism There are, roughly speaking, two definitions of photographic realism on the market: an epistemological and an ontological one. 3 I will briefly introduce both and argue them to be intertwined. This leads to a unified definition of photographic realism which, in the remainder of this paper, faces the challenge of incorporating digital photography. Photographs are epistemologically realistic because they are reliable informants about the visual properties of their depicta. Whereas a judge is probably not interested in a drawing of a murder, she is likely to be interested in a photograph of it. This is due to photography s mirror-like reflection of reality. Like mirrors, photographs can only depict real things and have limited possibilities to misrepresent them. In contrast to a painter, a photographer cannot decide to depict a black horse as purple. Emphasizing photography s objectivity, epistemological realists assign to it the function of informing us about the visual appearance things. 3 Maynard (1983, pp. 155-156). 116

Photographs are ontologically realistic because they are causal effects of their depicta. This ontological connection is an implication of how analog photographs are made: A chemical emulsion serves to capture rays of light reflecting from the depictum. The result can be compared with a footprint in the sand. The depictum has imprinted its visual appearance on the photographic material, just like the foot has imprinted its shape in the sand. Prints and photographs are the result of causal interaction between sand and foot or photo paper and depictum. Emphasizing this causal dimension of photography, ontological realists assign to it a reliclike function. We care for photographs as causal effects of their depicta. A photograph of my girlfriend, for example, matters to me in the same way as her lipstick marks at the end of a letter. Not because of the informational content expressed she could have expressed her love using conventional signs like x x x but because of the causal origin of this content. I care for the lipstick-markings because they are a causal effect of my girlfriend pushing her lips on the paper. Similarly, I do not care for my girlfriend s photograph as a source of information about her as if I could forget what she looks like but because there has been a physical connection between my girlfriend and the photograph. Epistemological and ontological realists agree that photographs have an intimate relation with reality. The former, however, defines this relation as one of adequate reflection, whereas the latter defines it in terms of a causal connection. However different these definitions of photographic realism might be, they are still intertwined as epistemological realism depends on ontological realism. Only because the informational content of the photograph is produced in a causal manner, do we take its content to be supremely veracious. What makes a photograph reliable is not itself some visible feature, but rather the causal origin of its visible features. In principle, a painting and a photograph can have the exact same content. Imagine someone showing you a highly detailed picture, which you take to be a photograph of your burning house. The person showing you the picture sees your panic and quickly reassures you that it is not a photograph but an extremely realistic looking painting. Although we still see the same picture the knowledge that the marking s of the picture s surface lack a causal origin does not change the picture as such there is a difference in our experience of it. As the content of the picture is not a causal effect of 117

the depictum, we know it does not necessarily represent a state of affairs. If the picture were a photograph we would have had a reason to despair, as photographs due to their causal origin can only show us the world like it is. 2. The Digital Challenge The idea that all photographs are realistic has been challenged by the rise of digital photography. Pictures produced with digital cameras would lack the realism of their analog predecessors. 4 Remember that analog photography s realism is an implication of its causal origin: a depictum imprints its visual appearance on a chemical emulsion. The digital camera, by contrast, does not use an emulsion, but scans the visual field, turning it into a grid consisting of a finite number of cells. Each of these cells is assigned a code specifying its color and shade. 5 Afterwards, these codes can be translated into visual information again and the depictum emerges. Hence, digital cameras do not seem to produce a representation which is causally related to the depictum, but rather one that refers to it with conventional signs, i.e. digital code. In this section, I present two ways in which digital photographs, because of their different technical origin, resist a realistic understanding. They would (a) not be epistemologically realistic, nor (b) would they be ontologically realistic. Digital photographs would not be epistemologically realistic, because they are not reliable carriers of information about the things they depict. The reason would be that they can be easily manipulated. According to Barbara Savedoff this is an implication of their code-based origin. 6 When I take a digital picture of something, the depictum s visual appearance is translated into code. This code can subsequently be altered, which produces changes in the way the depictum is represented. Hence, digital photographs can present their depicta inadequately, for example, as white in stead of black or as large in stead of small. Does the possibility to manipulate the visual content of a digital photograph present us with a knock-down argument against a realistic under- 4 Mitchell (1992, pp. 3-4). 5 Lister (2000, p. 311). 6 Savedoff (1997, p. 210). 118

standing of digital photography? For three reasons, I think it does not: First, every manipulation requires a realistic original which can subsequently be altered. Only because there is an epistemologically realistic original digital image on which a horse is black, can I produce one on which it is green. The possibility of manipulation cannot serve in an argument against digital photography s realism, as manipulation presupposes realism. Secondly, even manipulated photographs can be reliable informants about many aspects of their depicta. Consider a photographs of the pyramids at Giza on the cover of National Geographic. 7 In order to fit all three pyramids on the narrow front-page, the magazine adjusted the position of the pyramids, placing them slightly closer to another. Still, we are probably comfortable to admit that (a) this picture is a photograph of the pyramids at Giza and that (b) we can learn a lot about the pyramids from it. It provides us with information about their color and shape. We only suffer disappointment if we want to find out about their exact location, which is hard to find out using a photograph anyway. Thirdly, it has been argued that digital photographs are unrealistic because they are capable of depicting things that never existed. 8 There is, for example, a picture of a meeting between Tom Cruise and Dustin Hoffman which, in reality, never took place. Two digital photographs of the actors were merged to make it appear as if they had met. This case, however, is not an argument against the epistemological realism of the digital photograph either, because the picture in question the one in which Cruise and Hoffman appear to meet each other is not a photograph at all. It is a collage which uses epistemologically realistic photographic elements to produce a picture which is not a photograph. Photographic elements are used like paint to portray a fictional event. The material out of which this portrait is made are photographical, but the end product is not. Of course, this end-product is not photographically realistic, but as it is not a photograph, it cannot serve as proof for the hypothesis that digital pictures are (epistemologically) unrealistic. The possibility to manipulate digital photographs does not hinder an 7 Savedoff (1997, p. 211). 8 Savedoff (1997, p. 211). 119

(epistemologically) realistic view of digital photography. It does not, since manipulation requires an epistemologically realistic original, manipulated photographs are reliable informants about certain aspects of their depicta, and many unrealistic photographs are not photographs at all but collages. The more fundamental challenge to a realistic understanding of digital photography is not to be found in the possibilities of image manipulation. It rather lies at the heart of every unmanipulated digital photograph, and concerns its (lack of) ontological realism. Digital photographs would not be ontologically realistic, because they are not causal effects of their depicta. 9 To understand this thesis a brief comparison with their analog counterparts is useful. Remember that analog photographs are like footprints, as they have a double relation with their depicta. They are epistemologically intimate with them, as they reliably inform us about the things represented. But they also are ontologically intimate with them, as the depictum is a causal effect of the depictum. Just like a footprint is the result of physical contact between foot and sand, a photograph is the result of physical contact between depictum and picture. In the case of digital photography this ontological tie would be absent. The physical intimacy between picture and depictum appears to be interrupted by an intermediate level of code. What I see on a digital picture s surface is not the result of a thing imprinting its visual appearance on it, but of a certain constellation of digital code. Whereas analog photography is indexical in nature, i.e. causally related to its depictum, digital photography apparently lacks this causal connection. Rather then being a direct imprint of the visual appearance of the depictum, it is a reconstruction of its depictum on the basis of digital code. This implies, that the digital photograph and its depictum are never ontologically intimate with each other. The ontological lack of the digital photograph is best illustrated by means of analogy. Imagine a letter with lipstick-marks on it. Suppose a girl tells her boyfriend that these marks are not the product of lips being pushed against paper, but were drawn by an artist. This confession takes the magic surrounding the markings away, even if they perfectly resemble the shape of the girl s lips: they are not the effect of causal contact 9 Mitchell (1992, p. 4). 120

between the paper and the object of interest (the girl). Marks caused by physical contact between girl and paper have a surplus lacked by the drawn likeness. Although this surplus is invisible the fake marks and the actual marks may look perfectly alike it does affect our experience of them. Causal markings are preferred over the drawn ones, as they are closer to the real thing than the latter. 10 The digital photograph would suffer from a similar lack as the dawn lipstick-markings. Even when they are veracious representations of their depicta they would not be causally related to them. Their visual content is not an effect of causal interaction between photograph and depictum. Whereas an analog photograph is of its subject in a double sense it displays this subject and is an effect of it the digital picture can only be of its depictum in the first sense. The markings on its surface are not caused directly by the depictum, but by an underlying level of code which refers to the visual properties of the depictum with conventional signs. Thus, all digital pictures appear to lack ontological realism. I discussed two ways in which digital photography resists a realistic approach. The first challenge the possibility to manipulate digital photographs proved to be no real threat to a realistic understanding of photography. A second challenge is more serious: Every unmanipulated digital picture would lack a causal relation to its depictum. It might veraciously represents its depictum, but would not be physically connected with it. 3. Digital Realism The claim that digital photography is not realistic leads to an unpleasant dilemma. Either we conclude from it that realism is not an essential property of photography, as digital photography is not realistic. This is an undesirable outcome, as it leaves us without a criterion to distinguish photography from types of depiction that are not essentially realistic, like painting. Or we hold that realism is an essential property of photography and argue that the pictures made with a digital camera are not photographs. This outcome is undesirable too, because it is counterintuitive: in daily life we refer to pictures made with digital cameras as photographs. To avoid this dilemma, I argue that the assumption from which it originates 10 Maynard (1983, p. 159). 121

that digital photographs lack ontological realism is false. I take on the ontological challenge formulated in the previous section, and argue that digital photography is ontologically realistic too. How am I going to argue for this digital realism? Remember that ontological realists ascribe to analog photographs a relic-like function, based on their causal connection with the depictum. Now, if it is true that digital photographs lack ontological realism, one can reasonably expect they cannot perform this relic-like function. In the following, however, I discuss three examples in which digital photographs do function as relics. This is already an indication that there digital photography is more realistic than some argue. At the end of the section, I use my examples to develop a proper argument for digital photography s realism. Example 1. Suppose I keep a photograph of a deceased friend in my wallet. This picture is not primarily there to inform me about my friend s appearance, but rather to stay in touch with him. His photograph can perform this function because it is the effect of physical interaction between my late friend and the picture. In this sense, his photograph has an analogous meaning for me as, for example, his cigarette lighter, that was passed on to me after his death. I care for the lighter because my friend touched it; because there was physical contact between the lighter and my friend. Both in the lighter and the in the photograph something of my friend seems to be present. Not in a supernatural way, but simply because they were physically connected If digital pictures lack ontological realism, we can expect them to be unable to function as relics. Still, they seem very much able to function as such. Imagine a digital photograph of my friend used as wall-paper (i.e. as background-image) on my mobile phone. Is this digital picture there to inform me about the visual appearance of my friend? Probably not. It rather serves to keep in touch, i.e. to sustain contact with the depictum. Thus, digital photographs can also serve as relics, a function which is traditionally related to photography s ontological realism. Example 2. The surface of an analog photograph is integer. Suppose you have an analog photograph of a deceased friend in your office. One day, a colleague enters, takes a pen, and draws a moustache on your friend s 122

face. Most people consider this offensive, but why? The ontological realist would argue that drawing a moustache on a photograph is offensive because picture and depictum are ontologically close. When we draw on the photograph we do not just draw on a likeness of him, but on something which is physically connected with him. My friend is more present in the photograph than in a description or a drawing, which makes drawing on it especially inappropriate. Digital photographs, presumably unrealistic, have an integer surface too. Suppose someone downloads a digital photograph of your friend and digitally adds a moustache to his face. This action is just as impudent as adding a moustache to an analog photograph with a pen. Thus, a digital photograph can also be treated in way which is inappropriate towards its depictum, even though we know perfectly well that the depictum is not actually harmed by these actions. Both analog and digital photographs can be treated in a way that violates the integrity of the object displayed, which suggest they both are ontologically close to their depicta. Example 3. Whereas the first two examples serve as indications that digital photography might be more realistic than often assumed, a third one offers a springboard for a proper argument in favor of this conclusion. I first introduce this example and use it afterwards to make my argument against the claim that digital photography is not causally related to its depictum. Suppose I have a friend that recently passed away. As I have no photographs of him, I ask his brother to e-mail me one, which he does. Some days later, I run into my friend s brother and thank him for e-mailing me the picture. To my surprise, however, the brother admits that the picture he sent were not digital photographs, but pure simulations. His hard-drive crashed and he lost all his photographs, so he decided to reconstruct his brother s visual appearance out of raw digital code. The result is an apparently photographic picture portraying my friend. Although I see that this simulation adequately represents my friends appearance, I am probably disappointed. In an ideal world, I would have chosen a digital photograph over a mere simulation. In comparison with a simulation, which lacks any origin in reality, digital photographs suddenly appear to be ontologically intimate with their depicta. Whereas the simulation is the product of the intention s of a human subject, the real digital photograph displays a depic- 123

tum that was in front of a lens and caused certain constellations of digital code in the camera. These codes would not have been formed, and no picture would have been produced by them, if my friend had not been in front of the camera to cause them. This last example reveals the causal nature of digital photography: Only when a depictum with a certain visual appearance is in front of the lens, a particular constellation of codes can be formed in the digital camera. These codes can subsequently be translated back to the visual appearance of the depictum. In contrast to the pure simulation, constructed from scratch out of raw code, the digital camera produces its code in an entirely causal, non-intentional manner. Consequently, indexicality is a feature of digital photography too: The depictum causes certain codes, these codes cause markings on the picture s surface, and these markings allow me to see the depictum in the photograph. Of course, there is a longer chain of causes than in analog photography, but it is still a purely causal process in which reality creates its own picture. Although it is undeniable that analog and digital photography are different, one cannot hold that the former would be realistic and the latter is not. Both pictures are indexes, i.e. causally related to their depictum, be it that the analog photograph is so in a more direct way. In the case of digital photography, the marks on the picture s surface are not the direct effect of interaction between photograph and depictum, but they are indirectly. There is a direct causal link between the appearance of the depictum and the code in the camera, and there is a direct causal link between the code and the markings on the picture s surface. Analog and digital photography are both ultimately caused by the object or events in front of the lens. References Barthes, R. (1982). Camera Lucida: Reflections on Photography. New York, Hill and Wang. Lister, M. (2001). Photography in the Age of Electronic Imaging. In Wells, L. (ed.) (2000) Photography: A Critical Introduction. London, Routlegde, pp. 303-347. 124

Manyard, P. (1983). The Secular Icon: Photography and the Functions of Images. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 42, pp. 155-169. Mitchell. W. (1992). The Reconfigured Eye: Visual Truth in the Post- Photographic Era. London, MIT Press. Savedoff. B. (1997). Digital Imagery and the Resources of Photography. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 55, pp. 201-214. Walton, K. (2008). Transparent Pictures: On the Nature of Photographic Realism. In Walden, S. (ed.) (2008). Photography and Philosophy: Essays on the Pencil of Nature. Oxford, Blackwell, pp. 14-49. 125