GOLDEN AND SILVER RATIOS IN BARGAINING

Similar documents
THEORY: NASH EQUILIBRIUM

Summary Overview of Topics in Econ 30200b: Decision theory: strong and weak domination by randomized strategies, domination theorem, expected utility

CHAPTER LEARNING OUTCOMES. By the end of this section, students will be able to:

final examination on May 31 Topics from the latter part of the course (covered in homework assignments 4-7) include:

ECON 282 Final Practice Problems

Topic 1: defining games and strategies. SF2972: Game theory. Not allowed: Extensive form game: formal definition

Game Theory Refresher. Muriel Niederle. February 3, A set of players (here for simplicity only 2 players, all generalized to N players).

Strategic Bargaining. This is page 1 Printer: Opaq

Dynamic Programming in Real Life: A Two-Person Dice Game

Dynamic Games: Backward Induction and Subgame Perfection

Multi-Agent Bilateral Bargaining and the Nash Bargaining Solution

The Rubinstein bargaining game without an exogenous first-mover

International Economics B 2. Basics in noncooperative game theory

3 Game Theory II: Sequential-Move and Repeated Games

Game Theory and Randomized Algorithms

Extensive Games with Perfect Information. Start by restricting attention to games without simultaneous moves and without nature (no randomness).

Sequential Games When there is a sufficient lag between strategy choices our previous assumption of simultaneous moves may not be realistic. In these

FIRST PART: (Nash) Equilibria

The extensive form representation of a game

Microeconomics II Lecture 2: Backward induction and subgame perfection Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 4 Basics in Game Theory (2)

Dynamic games: Backward induction and subgame perfection

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Dice Games and Stochastic Dynamic Programming

Domination Rationalizability Correlated Equilibrium Computing CE Computational problems in domination. Game Theory Week 3. Kevin Leyton-Brown

Normal Form Games: A Brief Introduction

Stability of Cartels in Multi-market Cournot Oligopolies

Rationality and Common Knowledge

UPenn NETS 412: Algorithmic Game Theory Game Theory Practice. Clyde Silent Confess Silent 1, 1 10, 0 Confess 0, 10 5, 5

Extensive Form Games: Backward Induction and Imperfect Information Games

Extensive-Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games. Mihai Manea MIT

Permutation group and determinants. (Dated: September 19, 2018)

Game theory lecture 5. October 5, 2013

Introduction to Industrial Organization Professor: Caixia Shen Fall 2014 Lecture Note 6 Games and Strategy (ch.4)-continue

Econ 302: Microeconomics II - Strategic Behavior. Problem Set #5 June13, 2016

Cutting a Pie Is Not a Piece of Cake

Introduction to Game Theory

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

DYNAMIC GAMES. Lecture 6

Appendix A A Primer in Game Theory

CS510 \ Lecture Ariel Stolerman

8.F The Possibility of Mistakes: Trembling Hand Perfection

Game Theory. Lecture Notes By Y. Narahari. Department of Computer Science and Automation Indian Institute of Science Bangalore, India August 2012

1\2 L m R M 2, 2 1, 1 0, 0 B 1, 0 0, 0 1, 1

(a) Left Right (b) Left Right. Up Up 5-4. Row Down 0-5 Row Down 1 2. (c) B1 B2 (d) B1 B2 A1 4, 2-5, 6 A1 3, 2 0, 1

Pure strategy Nash equilibria in non-zero sum colonel Blotto games

Some introductory notes on game theory

Games in Extensive Form, Backward Induction, and Subgame Perfection:

1. Simultaneous games All players move at same time. Represent with a game table. We ll stick to 2 players, generally A and B or Row and Col.

Extensive Games with Perfect Information A Mini Tutorial

Resource Allocation and Decision Analysis (ECON 8010) Spring 2014 Foundations of Game Theory

CMU Lecture 22: Game Theory I. Teachers: Gianni A. Di Caro

Computing Nash Equilibrium; Maxmin

Best Response to Tight and Loose Opponents in the Borel and von Neumann Poker Models

Exercises for Introduction to Game Theory SOLUTIONS

Supplementary Appendix Commitment and (In)Efficiency: a Bargaining Experiment

ECON 312: Games and Strategy 1. Industrial Organization Games and Strategy

Game Theory. Department of Electronics EL-766 Spring Hasan Mahmood

Simultaneous-Move Games: Mixed Strategies. Games Of Strategy Chapter 7 Dixit, Skeath, and Reiley

2. The Extensive Form of a Game

Modeling Billiards Games

February 11, 2015 :1 +0 (1 ) = :2 + 1 (1 ) =3 1. is preferred to R iff

Using Game Theory to Analyze Physical Layer Cognitive Radio Algorithms

Bargaining games. Felix Munoz-Garcia. EconS Strategy and Game Theory Washington State University

Behavioral Strategies in Zero-Sum Games in Extensive Form

Student Name. Student ID

Asynchronous Best-Reply Dynamics

/633 Introduction to Algorithms Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Algorithmic Game Theory Date: 12/6/18

Non-Cooperative Game Theory

Mixed Strategies; Maxmin

6. Bargaining. Ryan Oprea. Economics 176. University of California, Santa Barbara. 6. Bargaining. Economics 176. Extensive Form Games

Game Theory ( nd term) Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi. Graduate School of Management and Economics Sharif University of Technology.

U strictly dominates D for player A, and L strictly dominates R for player B. This leaves (U, L) as a Strict Dominant Strategy Equilibrium.

Minmax and Dominance

Strategic Manipulation in Tournament Games

CSC304: Algorithmic Game Theory and Mechanism Design Fall 2016

Opponent Models and Knowledge Symmetry in Game-Tree Search

Lecture 6: Basics of Game Theory

Convergence in competitive games

Extensive Form Games and Backward Induction

Math 152: Applicable Mathematics and Computing

Games of Perfect Information and Backward Induction

ECON 301: Game Theory 1. Intermediate Microeconomics II, ECON 301. Game Theory: An Introduction & Some Applications

Computational Aspects of Game Theory Bertinoro Spring School Lecture 2: Examples

Extensive-Form Correlated Equilibrium: Definition and Computational Complexity

Extensive Form Games: Backward Induction and Imperfect Information Games

CSCI 699: Topics in Learning and Game Theory Fall 2017 Lecture 3: Intro to Game Theory. Instructor: Shaddin Dughmi

Medium Access Control via Nearest-Neighbor Interactions for Regular Wireless Networks

Simon Fraser University Fall 2014

Wythoff s Game. Kimberly Hirschfeld-Cotton Oshkosh, Nebraska

Game Theory: Introduction. Game Theory. Game Theory: Applications. Game Theory: Overview

How to divide things fairly

Chapter 3 Learning in Two-Player Matrix Games

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER SERIES. Stable Networks and Convex Payoffs. Robert P. Gilles Virginia Tech University

Game Theory Lecturer: Ji Liu Thanks for Jerry Zhu's slides

ECO 199 B GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 B February 24 SEQUENTIAL AND SIMULTANEOUS GAMES. Representation Tree Matrix Equilibrium concept

NORMAL FORM GAMES: invariance and refinements DYNAMIC GAMES: extensive form

Dynamic Games of Complete Information

Transcription:

GOLDEN AND SILVER RATIOS IN BARGAINING KIMMO BERG, JÁNOS FLESCH, AND FRANK THUIJSMAN Abstract. We examine a specific class of bargaining problems where the golden and silver ratios appear in a natural way. 1. Introduction There are five coins on a table to be divided among players 1 to 4. The players act in turns cyclically starting from player 1. When it is a player s turn, he has two options: to or to. If he s he earns a coin, the next two players get two coins each and the remaining player gets nothing. For example, if player 3 s then he gets one coin, players 4 and 1 get two coins each and player gets no coins. This way the game is repeated until someone s. If nobody ever s then they all get nothing. Each player can randomize between the two alternatives and maximizes his expected payoff. The game is presented in the figure below, where the players payoffs are shown as the components of the vectors. player 1 player player 3 player 4 (1,,, 0) (0, 1,, ) (, 0, 1, ) (,, 0, 1) Bargaining problems have been studied extensively in game theory literature [4, 6, 7]. Our game can be seen as a barganing problem where the players cannot make their own offers but can only accept or decline the given division. Furthermore, the game is a special case of a so-called sequential ting game which have been studied, for example, in [5, 9]. The prominent solution concept in such games is a Nash equilibrium, which defines the players moves such that no player can gain by any unilateral deviation. Moreover, we assume credible behavior throughout the play. Such subgame-perfect solutions exist by [5]. While studying structural properties of the subgame-perfect equilibria of the above game, we noticed that the golden ratio plays an important role in the strategies as well as in the distribution of payoffs. In particular, player 3 will get a corresponding payoff of ϕ = 1+ 5 1.618, player will get 3 ϕ and players 1 and 4 will get 1, i.e. the golden ratio is used to split the additional fifth coin in probability amongst players and 3. In further explorations, we observed that for several other games of this type, not only the golden but also the silver ratio appears in the solutions. A common feature of these games is that n players have to split n + 1 coins according to some specific rules. In this respect, we also relate to the earlier literature for dividing the dollar [1, ]. Kimmo Berg acknowledges funding from Emil Aaltosen Säätiö through Post doc -pooli. 1

The games examined here are closely related to ting games in which the players all move simultaneously. For that class of games, the existence of (approximate) equilibria is one of the most challenging open problems in the field of dynamic games (cf. [3, 8, 10, 11]).. The role of the golden ratio in the solutions In this section, we derive the equilibria for the above game and find that the golden ratio appears in the solution. Moreover, we extend the four-player game with cyclically symmetric payoff structure 1 (1,,, 0) to an n-player game with payoff structure (1, 1,..., 1,,, 0). In these games, a player s strategy defines the probability of ting for each turn he has. In general, a player could assign different probabilities for the first turn, the second turn and so on. However, we restrict our analysis to stationary strategies, where for each player the probability that he uses is the same in all turns. A Nash equilibrium specifies a strategy for each player such that it is a best response to the other players strategies. For example, if the player s with probability one, then it must be that the ting payoff is at least as high as the expected continuation payoff when ing, given the other players strategies. Subgame-perfection requires that the same strategies must also form a Nash equilibrium when any of the other players starts the game. Theorem.1. In the game with cyclically symmetric payoff structure (1,,, 0), there are only two stationary subgame-perfect equilibria and both of them are symmetric in the players strategies: (1) The strategy profile in which every player s with probability 1. The corresponding payoffs are (1,,, 0). () The strategy profile in which every player s with probability p = 3 5 = ϕ. According to this strategy profile, the overall probability that a certain player will eventually is given by the four-vector 1 3ϕ 4 ( ϕ, 3 + ϕ, 5 3ϕ, 8 + 5ϕ). The corresponding payoffs are (1, 3 ϕ, ϕ, 1). Remark: Notice how the Fibonacci numbers appear in the total ting probabilities mentioned in ():, 3, 5, 8, and 1,, 3, 5 as the multipliers of ϕ. In fact, the probability that the game will end at stage 1,, 3, 4,... is given respectively by: ϕ, 3 + ϕ, 5 3ϕ, 8 + 5ϕ, 13 8ϕ, 1 + 13ϕ, 34 1ϕ,.... Proof. Consider an arbitrary stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium and denote by p i the probability that player i {1,, 3, 4} puts on ting in each of his turns. We will only determine these ting probabilities p i, then the expressions for the corresponding payoffs follow easily. We distinguish three cases. Case 1: A player s with probability 1, i.e., p i = 1 for some player i {1,, 3, 4}. Due to the cyclic symmetry, we may assume without loss of generality that p 1 = 1. Consequently, it is the best response for player 4 to, thus p 4 = 1. Similarly, we obtain p 3 = 1 and p = 1. Since it is also player 1 s best response to, this results in a stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium, in which every player s with probability 1. 1 A cyclically symmetric payoff structure (a, b, c, d) is to be interpreted as given by the payoffs that players get upon ting by player 1; players get (d, a, b, c) if player s, etc. This means that the ting player always gets a, the next one b, etc. VOLUME, NUMBER

Case : A player s with probability 0, i.e., p i = 0 for some player i {1,, 3, 4}. We distinguish two subcases: (i) p i = 0 for all i {1,, 3, 4}, (ii) p i = 0 and p i+1 > 0 for some i. Subcase (i) is not an equilibrium since any player should if nobody is ting. In subcase (ii), the assumptions imply that player i 1 should, i.e., p i 1 = 0, as he then gets payoff. Now, this implies that p i = 0, which means that only player i + 1 is ting and this contradicts that p i = 0. Case 3: The players randomize between the alternatives, i.e., p i (0, 1) for every player i {1,, 3, 4}. In this case, every player i {1,, 3, 4} is indifferent between ting and continuing. Quitting yields payoff 1 for player i. However, if player i continues, then with probability p i+1 + (1 p i+1 )p i+ + (1 p i+1 )(1 p i+ )p i+3, one of the other players s before it is player i s turn again. Given that this happens, player i receives an expected payoff of C i := p i+1 0 + (1 p i+1 )p i+ + (1 p i+1 )(1 p i+ )p i+3 p i+1 + (1 p i+1 )p i+ + (1 p i+1 )(1 p i+ )p i+3. In the expression above, players 5, 6 and 7 are identified with players 1, and 3, respectively. Since player i is indifferent between ting and continuing, we have C i = 1 for every player i {1,, 3, 4}. Since C 1 = 1, we obtain Substituting (.1) into C = 1 yields Further substituting (.1) and (.) into C 3 = 1, we derive p 4 = p p 3 + p p 3 (1 p )(1 p 3 ). (.1) p 1 = p + p 3 p p 3 1 p. (.) p 3 = p + (p ) 3 5p + (p ), (.3) and then finally C 4 = 1 gives p = 3 5. After substitution, we find that p 1 = p = p 3 = p 4 = 3 5, which yields a symmetric stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium. We now extend the above four-player game with payoffs (1,,, 0) to an n-player game with payoffs (1, 1,..., 1,,, 0). This n-player game has a similar symmetric solution with corresponding payoffs (1, 1,..., 3 ϕ, ϕ, 1). The common ting probability p for each player in the n-player game satisfies the equation n 5 1 (1 p) n 1 = 0 p + p(1 p) + p(1 p) + p(1 p) 3 (1 p) i. Using that p(1 p) 3 n 5 i=0 (1 p)i = (1 p) 3 (1 (1 p) n 4 ), this simplifies to 1 (1 p) 3 = 0 p + p(1 p) + p(1 p), which is exactly the same equation that determines the solution to the four-player game. In the next section, we will see more games which have the golden ratio in the solution. MONTH YEAR 3 i=0

3. Different payoffs and the silver ratio In this section, we examine all possibilities of dividing the five coins among the four players. The symmetric stationary subgame-perfect equilibria can be computed in the same way as in the previous section and are presented in Table 1. In the first two lines, the stars mean that the payoffs can be anything as long as they are non-negative integers and sum up to five. The payoff structure (0,,, ) applies to (0, 1,, ) and (0, 3,, 0) for example. game ting probability corresponding payoffs (0,,, ) p = 0 (0, 0, 0, 0) (y x,,, x) p = 1 (y,,, x) (1, 0, 4, 0) p = ϕ 1 0.6 (1, ϕ, 1 + ϕ, 1) (1, 0.38,.6, 1) (1, 1, 3, 0) p = 1/ (1, 1,, 1) (1,,, 0) p = 1 1/ϕ 0.38 (1, 3 ϕ, ϕ, 1) (1, 1.38, 1.6, 1) (1, 3, 1, 0) p = 1 1/ 0.9 (1, 3,, 1) (1, 1.59, 1.41, 1) (1, 4, 0, 0) a p = 1 1/α 0.3 (1, 3 α, α, 1) (1, 1.70, 1.30, 1) (, 0, 0, 3) p = (3 3)/ 0.63 (, 3 1, 3, ) (, 0.73, 0.7, ) (1, 0,, ) has no symmetric stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium (1, y 3, x 1, ) has no symmetric stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium a Here α = ( 13 1)/. Table 1. The ting probabilities and the corresponding payoffs for symmetric stationary subgame-perfect equilibria in different games. We observe that the two games with the golden ratio, (1,,, 0) and (1, 0, 4, 0), are not the only ones that give a special way to divide the extra coin. All the expected payoffs of player 3, i.e., 1 + ϕ,, ϕ, and ( 13 1)/, are related to the silver ratio or the silver means. In fact, the golden ratio ϕ is also the first silver mean. The number is the second silver mean minus one and the number ( 13 1)/ is the third silver mean minus two. The number is related to the zeroth silver mean. Thus, player 3 receives some special fraction in each case. The game with payoffs (1, 0,, ) has no stationary subgame-perfect equilibrium, but it does have a cyclic subgame-perfect equilibrium where the players in the order 1, 4, 3,,... with common probability 1 1/ϕ. The corresponding payoffs are (1, ϕ, ϕ, 1). Note that the games (1, y 3, x 1, ) have non-symmetric stationary equilibria, where either p 1 = p 3 = 1 and p = p 4 = 0, or p 1 = p 3 = 0 and p = p 4 = 1. We remark that all the four-player games with payoffs (1, x, 4 x, 0) can be extended to n-player games with payoffs (1, 1,..., 1, x, 4 x, 0), while the equilibrium probabilities and corresponding payoffs preserve the golden and silver ratios like in the example at the end of Section. 4. Concluding remarks In the previous sections we have demonstrated how some of the golden ratio solutions can be extended to games with more than four players. Conversely, there is no straightforward way to find which n-player games of this type have solutions based on the golden ratio. The reason is that any such analysis involves solving higher order polynomial equations. 4 VOLUME, NUMBER

References [1] N. Anbarci, Divide-the-Dollar Game Revisited, Theory and Decision, 50 (001), 95-304 [] S. J. Brams and A. D. Taylor, Divide the Dollar: Three Solutions and Extensions, Theory and Decisions, 37 (1994), 11-31 [3] J. Flesch, F. Thuijsman, K. Vrieze, Cyclic Markov Equilibria in Stochastic Games, International Journal of Game Theory, 6 (1997), 303-314 [4] D. Fudenberg and J. Tirole, Game Theory, The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1991 [5] A. Mashiah-Yaakovi, Periodic Stopping Games, International Journal of Game Theory, 38 (009), 169-181 [6] J. F. Nash, The Bargaining Problem, Econometrica, 18 (1950), 155-16 [7] A. Rubinstein, Perfect Equilibrium in a Barganing Model, Econometrica, 50 (198), 97-109 [8] E. Solan and N. Vieille, Quitting Games An Example, International Journal of Game Theory, 31 (00), 365-381 [9] E. Solan and N. Vieille, Deterministic Multi-Player Dynkin Games, Journal of Mathematical Economics, 39 (003), 911-99 [10] N. Vieille, Two-Player Stochastic Games I: A Reduction, Israel Journal of Mathematics, 119 (000), 55-91 [11] N. Vieille, Two-Player Stochastic Games II: The Case of Recursive Games, Israel Journal of Mathematics, 119 (000), 93-16 MSC010: 11B39, 91A0, 91B6 Department of Mathematics and Systems Analysis, Aalto University School of Science, P.O. Box 11100, FI-00076 Aalto, Finland E-mail address: kimmo.berg@aalto.fi Department of Quantitative Economics, Maastricht University, The Netherlands E-mail address: j.flesch@maastrichtuniversity.nl Department of Knowledge Engineering, Maastricht University, The Netherlands E-mail address: f.thuijsman@maastrichtuniversity.nl MONTH YEAR 5