Convergence in competitive games

Similar documents
Domination Rationalizability Correlated Equilibrium Computing CE Computational problems in domination. Game Theory Week 3. Kevin Leyton-Brown

Game Theory and Randomized Algorithms

Games in Networks and connections to algorithms. Éva Tardos Cornell University

Introduction to Algorithms / Algorithms I Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Algorithms and Game Theory Date: 12/4/14

Minmax and Dominance

Chapter 3 Learning in Two-Player Matrix Games

Topic 1: defining games and strategies. SF2972: Game theory. Not allowed: Extensive form game: formal definition

Network-building. Introduction. Page 1 of 6

Lectures: Feb 27 + Mar 1 + Mar 3, 2017

Section Notes 6. Game Theory. Applied Math 121. Week of March 22, understand the difference between pure and mixed strategies.

/633 Introduction to Algorithms Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Algorithmic Game Theory Date: 12/6/18

Game Theory. Vincent Kubala

Game Theory. Vincent Kubala

CS510 \ Lecture Ariel Stolerman

Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory. Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2014 Prof. Michael Kearns

The extensive form representation of a game

Extensive-Form Games with Perfect Information

Noncooperative Games COMP4418 Knowledge Representation and Reasoning

Problem 1 (15 points: Graded by Shahin) Recall the network structure of our in-class trading experiment shown in Figure 1

Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory. Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2016 Prof. Michael Kearns

CSCI 699: Topics in Learning and Game Theory Fall 2017 Lecture 3: Intro to Game Theory. Instructor: Shaddin Dughmi

Multiplayer Pushdown Games. Anil Seth IIT Kanpur

final examination on May 31 Topics from the latter part of the course (covered in homework assignments 4-7) include:

Auctions as Games: Equilibria and Efficiency Near-Optimal Mechanisms. Éva Tardos, Cornell

FIRST PART: (Nash) Equilibria

Resource Allocation and Decision Analysis (ECON 8010) Spring 2014 Foundations of Game Theory

Computing Nash Equilibrium; Maxmin

Dynamic Games: Backward Induction and Subgame Perfection

Stanford University CS261: Optimization Handout 9 Luca Trevisan February 1, 2011

Dynamic Games of Complete Information

Cognitive Radios Games: Overview and Perspectives

Computational aspects of two-player zero-sum games Course notes for Computational Game Theory Section 3 Fall 2010

Lecture 6: Basics of Game Theory

Summary Overview of Topics in Econ 30200b: Decision theory: strong and weak domination by randomized strategies, domination theorem, expected utility

LECTURE 26: GAME THEORY 1

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 4 Basics in Game Theory (2)

Multiple Agents. Why can t we all just get along? (Rodney King)

ECON 282 Final Practice Problems

Math 464: Linear Optimization and Game

Learning, prediction and selection algorithms for opportunistic spectrum access

CSC304 Lecture 3. Game Theory (More examples, PoA, PoS) CSC304 - Nisarg Shah 1

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 4

3 Game Theory II: Sequential-Move and Repeated Games

Near-Optimal Radio Use For Wireless Network Synch. Synchronization

Extensive Games with Perfect Information. Start by restricting attention to games without simultaneous moves and without nature (no randomness).

Game Theory: The Basics. Theory of Games and Economics Behavior John Von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (1943)

Routing in Max-Min Fair Networks: A Game Theoretic Approach

Normal Form Games: A Brief Introduction

Game Theory and MANETs: A Brief Tutorial

The Cauchy Criterion

Modeling the Dynamics of Coalition Formation Games for Cooperative Spectrum Sharing in an Interference Channel

GOLDEN AND SILVER RATIOS IN BARGAINING

Extensive Form Games. Mihai Manea MIT

p-percent Coverage in Wireless Sensor Networks

NORMAL FORM GAMES: invariance and refinements DYNAMIC GAMES: extensive form

Throttling numbers for cop vs gambler

Mixed Strategies; Maxmin

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium

Instability of Scoring Heuristic In games with value exchange, the heuristics are very bumpy Make smoothing assumptions search for "quiesence"

Cross-Layer Game Theoretic Mechanism for Tactical Mobile Networks

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications. Kousha Etessami

Games in Extensive Form

Control of the Contract of a Public Transport Service

Networks and Games. Brighten Godfrey Discover Engineering CS Camp July 24, slides by Brighten Godfrey unless otherwise noted

Communication complexity as a lower bound for learning in games

Some recent results and some open problems concerning solving infinite duration combinatorial games. Peter Bro Miltersen Aarhus University

Repeated Games. Economics Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior. Shih En Lu. Simon Fraser University (with thanks to Anke Kessler)

Graphs and Network Flows IE411. Lecture 14. Dr. Ted Ralphs

SF2972 GAME THEORY Normal-form analysis II

Interference-Aware Joint Routing and TDMA Link Scheduling for Static Wireless Networks

Design of intelligent surveillance systems: a game theoretic case. Nicola Basilico Department of Computer Science University of Milan

Lecture 10: September 2

Chapter 2 Basics of Game Theory

Game Theory Lecturer: Ji Liu Thanks for Jerry Zhu's slides

Asynchronous Best-Reply Dynamics

A Survey on Supermodular Games

Extensive-Form Correlated Equilibrium: Definition and Computational Complexity

Game Theory: Introduction. Game Theory. Game Theory: Applications. Game Theory: Overview

SF2972: Game theory. Mark Voorneveld, February 2, 2015

Reading Robert Gibbons, A Primer in Game Theory, Harvester Wheatsheaf 1992.

Heuristic Search with Pre-Computed Databases

n-person Games in Normal Form

1. Introduction to Game Theory

CMU-Q Lecture 20:

G5212: Game Theory. Mark Dean. Spring 2017

Lecture 2. 1 Nondeterministic Communication Complexity

Robust Algorithms For Game Play Against Unknown Opponents. Nathan Sturtevant University of Alberta May 11, 2006

Exploiting Social Tie Structure for Cooperative Wireless Networking: A Social Group Utility Maximization Framework

Modeling, Analysis and Optimization of Networks. Alberto Ceselli

International Economics B 2. Basics in noncooperative game theory

ebay in the Sky: StrategyProof Wireless Spectrum Auctions

Advanced Microeconomics (Economics 104) Spring 2011 Strategic games I

Econ 302: Microeconomics II - Strategic Behavior. Problem Set #5 June13, 2016

Game theory Computational Models of Cognition

CS224W: Social and Information Network Analysis Jure Leskovec, Stanford University

Online Frequency Assignment in Wireless Communication Networks

Notes for Recitation 3

Multicasting over Multiple-Access Networks

CS188 Spring 2014 Section 3: Games

Extensive Games with Perfect Information A Mini Tutorial

Transcription:

Convergence in competitive games Vahab S. Mirrokni Computer Science and AI Lab. (CSAIL) and Math. Dept., MIT. This talk is based on joint works with A. Vetta and with A. Sidiropoulos, A. Vetta DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.1/8

Cut game Cut game: Players: Nodes of the graph. Player s strategy {1, 1} (Republican or Democrat) An action profile corresponds to a cut. Payoff: Total Contribution in the cut. Change Party if you gain. 1 3 3 4 3 5 Cut Value: 7 and 5 are unhappy. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p./8

The Cut Game: Price of Anarchy 1 3 3 5 3 4 1 3 3 4 3 5 Cut Value: 7 and 5 are unhappy. Cut Value: 8 Pure Nash Equilibrium. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.3/8

The Cut Game: Price of Anarchy 1 3 3 5 3 4 1 3 3 4 3 3 5 Cut Value: 7 Cut Value: 1 and 5 are unhappy. The Optimum. Social Function: The cut value. Price of Anarchy for this instance: 1 8 = 1.5. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.3/8

Outline Performance in lack of Coordination: Price of Anarchy. Best-Responses, Convergence, and Random Paths. A Potential Game: Cut Game Lower Bounds: Long poor paths Upper Bounds: random paths Basic-utility and Valid-utility Games Basic-utility Games: Fast Convergence. Valid-utility Games: Poor Sink Equilibria Conclusion: Other Games? DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.4/8

Convergence to Approximate Solutions We can model selfish behavior of players by a sequence of best responses by players. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.5/8

Convergence to Approximate Solutions We can model selfish behavior of players by a sequence of best responses by players. How fast do players converge to a Nash equilibrium? DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.5/8

Convergence to Approximate Solutions We can model selfish behavior of players by a sequence of best responses by players. How fast do players converge to a Nash equilibrium? How fast do players converge to an approximate solution? DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.5/8

Convergence to Approximate Solutions We can model selfish behavior of players by a sequence of best responses by players. How fast do players converge to a Nash equilibrium? How fast do players converge to an approximate solution? Our goal: How fast do players converge to an approximate solution? DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.5/8

Fair Paths In a fair path, we should let each player play at least once after each polynomially many steps. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.6/8

Fair Paths In a fair path, we should let each player play at least once after each polynomially many steps. One-round path: We let each player play once in a round. random path: We pick the next player at random. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.6/8

Fair Paths In a fair path, we should let each player play at least once after each polynomially many steps. One-round path: We let each player play once in a round. random path: We pick the next player at random. We are interested in the Social Value at the end of a fair path. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.6/8

A Cut game: The Party Affiliation Game Cut game: 1 3 3 4 3 5 Cut Value: 7 and 5 are unhappy. Social Function: The Cut Value Total Happiness Price of anarchy: at most. Local search algorithm for Max-Cut! DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.7/8

A Cut game: The Party Affiliation Game Cut game: 1 3 3 4 3 5 Cut Value: 7 and 5 are unhappy. Social Function: The Cut Value Convergence: Finding local optimum for Max-Cut is PLS-complete (Schaffer, Yannakakis [1991]). DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.7/8

Cut Game: Paths to Nash equilibria Unweighted graphs After O(n ) steps, we converge to a Nash equilibrium. Weighted graphs: It is PLS-complete. PLS-Complete problems and tight PLS reduction (Johnson, Papadimitriou, Yannakakis [1988]). Tight PLS reduction from Max-Cut (Schaffer, Yannakakis [1991]) There are some states that are exponentially far from any Nash equilibrium. Question: Are there long poor fair paths? DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.8/8

Cut Game: A Bad Example Consider graph G, a line of n vertices. The weight of edges are 1, 1 + n 1, 1 + n n 1,...,1 + n. Vertices are labelled 1,...,n throughout the line. Consider the round of best responses: 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.9/8

A Bad Example: Illustration 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+1/n 1+/n 1 1+n /n 1+n 1/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n After one move. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.10/8

A Bad Example: Illustration 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+1/n 1+/n 1 1+/n 1+1/n 1 1+n /n 1+n /n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n 1+n 1/n 1+n 1/n After two moves. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.10/8

A Bad Example: Illustration 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+1/n 1+/n 1 1+/n 1+1/n 1 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n 1+1/n 1+n /n After n moves (one round) DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.10/8

A Bad Example: Illustration 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n After two rounds. 1 1+1/n 1+/n 1+n /n 1+n 1/n Theorem: In the above example, the cut value after k rounds is O( n k ) of the optimum. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.10/8

Random One-round paths Theorem:(M., Sidiropoulos[004]) The expected value of the cut after a random one-round path is at most 1 8 of the optimum. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.11/8

Random One-round paths Theorem:(M., Sidiropoulos[004]) The expected value of the cut after a random one-round path is at most 1 8 of the optimum. Proof Sketch: The sum of payoffs of nodes after their moves is 1 -approximation. In a random ordering, with a constant probability a node occurs after 3 4 of its neighbors. The expected contribution of a node in the cut is a constant-factor of its total weight. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.11/8

Exponentially Long Poor Paths Theorem: (M., Sidiropoulos[004]) There exists a weighted graph G = (V (G),E(G)), with V (G) = Θ(n), and exponentially long fair path such that the value of the cut at the end of P, is at most O(1/n) of the optimum cut. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.1/8

Exponentially Long Poor Paths Theorem: (M., Sidiropoulos[004]) There exists a weighted graph G = (V (G),E(G)), with V (G) = Θ(n), and exponentially long fair path such that the value of the cut at the end of P, is at most O(1/n) of the optimum cut. Proof Sketch: Use the example for the exponentially long paths to the Nash equilibrium in the cut game. Find a player, v, that moves exponentially many times. Add a line of n vertices to this graph and connect all the vertices to player v. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.1/8

Poor Long Path: Illustration v 3 4 n 1 DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.13/8

Poor Long Path: Illustration v v 3 4 n 3 4 n 1 1 v n n 1 3 n 1 v 1 3 n 1 3 4 n v 1 DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.14/8

Mildly Greedy Players A Player is -greedy, if she does not move if she cannot double her payoff. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.15/8

Mildly Greedy Players A Player is -greedy, if she does not move if she cannot double her payoff. Theorem:(M., Sidiropoulos[004]) One round of selfish behavior of -greedy players converges to a constant-factor cut. Proof Idea: If a player moves it improves the value of the cut by a constant factor of its contribution in the cut. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.15/8

Mildly Greedy Players A Player is -greedy, if she does not move if she cannot double her payoff. Theorem:(M., Sidiropoulos[004]) One round of selfish behavior of -greedy players converges to a constant-factor cut. Proof Idea: If a player moves it improves the value of the cut by a constant factor of its contribution in the cut. Message: Mildly Greedy Players converge faster. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.15/8

Mildly Greedy Players A Player is -greedy, if she does not move if she cannot double her payoff. Theorem:(M., Sidiropoulos[004]) One round of selfish behavior of -greedy players converges to a constant-factor cut. Proof Idea: If a player moves it improves the value of the cut by a constant factor of its contribution in the cut. Message: Mildly Greedy Players converge faster. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.15/8

A Cut game: Total Happiness Cut game: The happiness of player v is equal to his total contribution in the cut minus the weight of its adjacent edges not in the cut. Social Function: Total Happiness: Sum of happiness of players DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.16/8

A Cut game: Total Happiness Cut game: The happiness of player v is equal to his total contribution in the cut minus the weight of its adjacent edges not in the cut. Social Function: Total Happiness: Sum of happiness of players In the context of correlation clustering: Maximizing agreement minus disagreement (Bansal, Blum, Chawla[00]). log n-approximation algorithm is known. (Charikar, Wirth[004]). DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.16/8

A Cut game: Total Happiness Cut game: The happiness of player v is equal to his total contribution in the cut minus the weight of its adjacent edges not in the cut. Social Function: Total Happiness: Sum of happiness of players Price of anarchy: unbounded in the worst case. A bad example: a cycle of size four. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.16/8

A Cut game: Total Happiness Cut game: The happiness of player v is equal to his total contribution in the cut minus the weight of its adjacent edges not in the cut. Social Function: Total Happiness: Sum of happiness of players The expected happiness of a random cut is zero. Our result: For unweighted graphs of large girth, if we start from a random cut, then after a random one-round path, the expected happiness is a sublogarthmic-approximation. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.16/8

Cut Game: Total Happiness For some δ > 0, we call an edge of G, δ-good, if at least one of its end-points, has degree at most δ. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.17/8

Cut Game: Total Happiness For some δ > 0, we call an edge of G, δ-good, if at least one of its end-points, has degree at most δ. For a pair u,v V (G), let E u,v denote the event that there exists a path p = x 1,x,...,x p, with u = x 1, and v = x p, and for any i, with 1 i < p, x i x i+1. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.17/8

Cut Game: Total Happiness For some δ > 0, we call an edge of G, δ-good, if at least one of its end-points, has degree at most δ. For a pair u,v V (G), let E u,v denote the event that there exists a path p = x 1,x,...,x p, with u = x 1, and v = x p, and for any i, with 1 i < p, x i x i+1. Lemma: Let {u,v}, {v,w} E(G), such that u w v. There exists a constant C, such that if the girth of G is at least C log n log log n, then Pr[E u,w] < n 3. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.17/8

Cut Game: Total Happiness For some δ > 0, we call an edge of G, δ-good, if at least one of its end-points, has degree at most δ. For a pair u,v V (G), let E u,v denote the event that there exists a path p = x 1,x,...,x p, with u = x 1, and v = x p, and for any i, with 1 i < p, x i x i+1. Lemma: Let {u,v}, {v,w} E(G), such that u w v. There exists a constant C, such that if the girth of G is at least C log n log log n, then Pr[E u,w] < n 3. Lemma: For any e E(G), we have Pr[e is cut ] 1/ o(1). DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.17/8

Cut Game: Total Happiness Lemma: Let e = {u,v} E(G), with u v, and deg(v) δ. Then, Pr[e is cut ] 1/ + Ω(1/ δ). DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.18/8

Cut Game: Total Happiness Lemma: Let e = {u,v} E(G), with u v, and deg(v) δ. Then, Pr[e is cut ] 1/ + Ω(1/ δ). Theorem: (M., Sidiropoulos[004]) There exists a constant C, such that for any C > C, and for any unweighted simple graph of girth at least C log n log log n, if we start from a random cut, the expected value of the happiness at the end of a random one-round path, is within a 1 (log n) O(1/C) factor from the maximum happiness. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.18/8

Outline Performance in lack of Coordination: Price of Anarchy. State Graphs, Convergence, and Fair Paths. Cut Games: Party Affiliation Games Lower Bounds: Long poor paths Upper Bounds: random paths Total Happiness: Cut minus Other Edges Basic-utility and Valid-utility Games. Basic-utility Games: Fast Convergence. Valid-utility Games: Poor Sink Equilibria! Conclusion: Other Games? DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.19/8

Valid-Utility Games Ground Set of Markets: V = {v 1,v,...,v n }. Player i can provide a subset of V. S i is a family of subsets of V feasible for player i. S i V is the strategy of player i. S i S i. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.0/8

Valid-Utility Games Ground Set of Markets: V = {v 1,v,...,v n }. Player i can provide a subset of V. S i is a family of subsets of V feasible for player i. S i V is the strategy of player i. S i S i. Social Function: A submodular set function f : V R on union of strategies: f( 1 i n S i ). DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.0/8

Valid-Utility Games Ground Set of Markets: V = {v 1,v,...,v n }. Player i can provide a subset of V. S i is a family of subsets of V feasible for player i. S i V is the strategy of player i. S i S i. Social Function: A submodular set function f : V R on union of strategies: f( 1 i n S i ). The payoff of any player is at least the change that he makes in the social function by playing. The sum of payoffs is at most the social function. Several examples, including the market sharing game and a facility location game DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.0/8

Valid-Utility Games Ground Set of Markets: V = {v 1,v,...,v n }. Player i can provide a subset of V. S i is a family of subsets of V feasible for player i. S i V is the strategy of player i. S i S i. Social Function: A submodular set function f : V R on union of strategies: f( 1 i n S i ). The payoff of any player is at least the change that he makes in the social function by playing. The sum of payoffs is at most the social function. In basic-utility games, the payoff is equal to the change that a player makes. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.0/8

Example: Market Sharing Game Market Sharing Game n markets and m players. Market i has a value q i and cost C i. Player j has a budget B j. Player j s action is to choose a subset of markets of his interest whose total cost is at most B j. The value of a market is divided equally between players that provide these markets. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.1/8

Example: Market Sharing Game Market Sharing Game n markets and m players. Market i has a value q i and cost C i. Player j has a budget B j. Player j s action is to choose a subset of markets of his interest whose total cost is at most B j. The value of a market is divided equally between players that provide these markets. Social Function: Total query that s satisfied in the market. (submodular.) DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.1/8

Valid-utility Games: Price of Anarchy Theorem:(Vetta[00]) The price of anarchy (of a mixed Nash equilibrium) in valid-utility games is at most. Theorem:(Vetta[00]) Basic-utility games are potential games. In particular, best responses will converge to a pure Nash equilibrium. Theorem:(Goemans, Li, Mirrokni, Thottan[004]) Pure Nash equilibria exist for market sharing games and can be found in polynomial time in the uniform case. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p./8

Basic-Utility Games : Convergence Theorem:(M.,Vetta[004]) In basic-utility games, after one round of selfish behavior of players, they converge to a 1 3-optimal solution. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.3/8

Market Sharing Games : Convergence Theorem:(M.,Vetta[004]) In basic-utility games, after one round of selfish behavior of players, they converge to a 1 3-optimal solution. Theorem: (M., Vetta[004]) In a market sharing game, after one round of selfish behavior of players, they 1 converge to a log(n) -optimal solution and this is almost tight. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.3/8

Valid-utility Games: Convergence Theorem:(M., Vetta[004]) For any k > 0, in valid-utility games, the social value after k rounds might be 1 n of the optimal social value. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.4/8

Sink Equilibria A sink equilibrium is a minimal set of states such that no best response move of any player goes out of these states. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.5/8

Sink Equilibria A sink equilibrium is a minimal set of states such that no best response move of any player goes out of these states. If we enter a sink equilibrium, we are stuck there. Even random best-response paths cannot help us going out of a sink equilibria. Price of anarchy for sink equilibria vs. the price of anarchy for Nash equilibria. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.5/8

Sink Equilibria Theorem: (M., Vetta) In valid-utility games, even though the price of anarchy for Nash equilibria is 1, the price of anarchy for sink equilibria is 1 n. The performance of the Nash equilibria (or the price of anarchy for NE) is not a good measure for these games. Theorem: (M., Vetta) Finding a sink equilibrium in valid-utility games is PLS-Hard and there are states that are exponentially far from any sink equilibria. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.6/8

Sink Equilibria Theorem: (M., Vetta) In valid-utility games, even though the price of anarchy for Nash equilibria is 1, the price of anarchy for sink equilibria is 1 n. The performance of the Nash equilibria (or the price of anarchy for NE) is not a good measure for these games. Theorem: (M., Vetta) Finding a sink equilibrium in valid-utility games is PLS-Hard and there are states that are exponentially far from any sink equilibria. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.6/8

Conclusion Study Speed of convergence to approximates solutions instead of to Nash equilibria. Sink equilibria: an alternative measure to study the performance of the systems in lack of coordination. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.7/8

Open problems Are there exponentially long fair paths in Basic-utility games. Is finding a -approximate Nash equilibrium for the cut game in P? How long does it take that -greedy players converge to a (-approximate) Nash equilibrium? If it is polynomial, then finding a -approximate Nash equilibrium is in P. Are there exponentially long paths in the market sharing game? Study covering and random paths in other games. DIMACS Bounded Rationality January, 005 p.8/8