To wards Empirical and Scientific Theories of Computation

Similar documents
Title? Alan Turing and the Theoretical Foundation of the Information Age

Adding Methodological Testing to Naur s Anti-formalism

Awareness and Understanding in Computer Programs A Review of Shadows of the Mind by Roger Penrose

R&D Meets Production: The Dark Side

Introduction to Computer Science

8.F The Possibility of Mistakes: Trembling Hand Perfection

5.4 Imperfect, Real-Time Decisions

Two Perspectives on Logic

Computation. Philosophical Issues. Instructor: Viola Schiaffonati. March, 26 th 2018

of the hypothesis, but it would not lead to a proof. P 1

REINTERPRETING 56 OF FREGE'S THE FOUNDATIONS OF ARITHMETIC

Philosophical Foundations

Is Artificial Intelligence an empirical or a priori science?

DVA325 Formal Languages, Automata and Models of Computation (FABER)

Lecture 19 November 6, 2014

Logical Agents (AIMA - Chapter 7)

11/18/2015. Outline. Logical Agents. The Wumpus World. 1. Automating Hunt the Wumpus : A different kind of problem

A NUMBER THEORY APPROACH TO PROBLEM REPRESENTATION AND SOLUTION

Fall Can Baykan. Arch467 Design Methods

Logic and the Sizes of Sets

Philosophy. AI Slides (5e) c Lin

CDT314 FABER Formal Languages, Automata and Models of Computation MARK BURGIN INDUCTIVE TURING MACHINES

Bricken Technologies Corporation Presentations: Bricken Technologies Corporation Corporate: Bricken Technologies Corporation Marketing:

THE RISE AND FALL OF THE CHURCH-TURING THESIS Mark Burgin

Overview: The works of Alan Turing ( )

Progress in Computer Science and Applied Logic

Jamie Mulholland, Simon Fraser University

THE GAME OF HEX: THE HIERARCHICAL APPROACH. 1. Introduction

Mathematical Proof of Four-Color Theorem. By Liu Ran. After examining a wide variety of different planar graphs, one discovers

Lecture 18 - Counting

Artificial Intelligence

CSCI 1590 Intro to Computational Complexity

Intelligent Agents. Introduction to Planning. Ute Schmid. Cognitive Systems, Applied Computer Science, Bamberg University. last change: 23.

Game Theory and Randomized Algorithms

Optimisation and Operations Research

Permutation Polynomials Modulo 2 w

arxiv:cs/ v2 [cs.cc] 27 Jul 2001

Artificial Intelligence

An Optimal Algorithm for a Strategy Game

@CRC Press. Discrete Mathematics. with Ducks. sarah-marie belcastro. let this be your watchword. serious mathematics treated with levity

1. MacBride s description of reductionist theories of modality

Wythoff s Game. Kimberly Hirschfeld-Cotton Oshkosh, Nebraska

Turing Centenary Celebration

AI Principles, Semester 2, Week 1, Lecture 2, Cognitive Science and AI Applications. The Computational and Representational Understanding of Mind

Artificial Intelligence

Tutorial 1. (ii) There are finite many possible positions. (iii) The players take turns to make moves.

From a Ball Game to Incompleteness

A MOVING-KNIFE SOLUTION TO THE FOUR-PERSON ENVY-FREE CAKE-DIVISION PROBLEM

FORMAL DEFINITION OF ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE 1

MAT Modular arithmetic and number theory. Modular arithmetic

Greedy Flipping of Pancakes and Burnt Pancakes

A variation on the game SET

Alessandro Cincotti School of Information Science, Japan Advanced Institute of Science and Technology, Japan

Pattern Avoidance in Unimodal and V-unimodal Permutations

Research Methods in Computer Science Lecture 4: Research process models

Tiling Problems. This document supersedes the earlier notes posted about the tiling problem. 1 An Undecidable Problem about Tilings of the Plane

Course Unit Outline 2017/18

Bibliography. S. Gill Williamson

COEN7501: Formal Hardware Verification

Formally Verified Endgame Tables

Design of intelligent surveillance systems: a game theoretic case. Nicola Basilico Department of Computer Science University of Milan

THE ENUMERATION OF PERMUTATIONS SORTABLE BY POP STACKS IN PARALLEL

18.204: CHIP FIRING GAMES

A Definition of Artificial Intelligence

THE BRITISH MATHEMATICIAN, COMPUTER PIOneer,

Introduction to Artificial Intelligence: cs580

Tangent: Boromean Rings. The Beer Can Game. Plan. A Take-Away Game. Mathematical Games I. Introduction to Impartial Combinatorial Games

The Chinese Remainder Theorem

Oracle Turing Machine. Kaixiang Wang

Surreal Numbers and Games. February 2010

Wilson s Theorem and Fermat s Theorem

CITS2211 Discrete Structures Turing Machines

Strict Finitism Refuted? Ofra Magidor ( Preprint of paper forthcoming Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 2007)

TOPOLOGY, LIMITS OF COMPLEX NUMBERS. Contents 1. Topology and limits of complex numbers 1

Math 127: Equivalence Relations

From Wireless Network Coding to Matroids. Rico Zenklusen

PAPER. Connecting the dots. Giovanna Roda Vienna, Austria

Artificial Intelligence: An Introduction

depth parallel time width hardware number of gates computational work sequential time Theorem: For all, CRAM AC AC ThC NC L NL sac AC ThC NC sac

Mark Kozek. December 7, 2010

Cutting a Pie Is Not a Piece of Cake

Preface for Instructors and Other Teachers 1 About This Book... xvii

Hamming Codes as Error-Reducing Codes

The congruence relation has many similarities to equality. The following theorem says that congruence, like equality, is an equivalence relation.

Primitive Roots. Chapter Orders and Primitive Roots

Intelligent Systems. Lecture 1 - Introduction

Adaptive Fault Diagnosis using Self-Referential Reasoning by Robert Cowen

ECS 20 (Spring 2013) Phillip Rogaway Lecture 1

Artificial Intelligence: An overview

37 Game Theory. Bebe b1 b2 b3. a Abe a a A Two-Person Zero-Sum Game

CS 771 Artificial Intelligence. Adversarial Search

Algorithms and Complexity for Japanese Puzzles

Permutation Generation Method on Evaluating Determinant of Matrices

Contents. MA 327/ECO 327 Introduction to Game Theory Fall 2017 Notes. 1 Wednesday, August Friday, August Monday, August 28 6

A Real-Time Algorithm for the (n 2 1)-Puzzle

On Drawn K-In-A-Row Games

ON THE EVOLUTION OF TRUTH. 1. Introduction

Lecture 2. 1 Nondeterministic Communication Complexity

A 2-Approximation Algorithm for Sorting by Prefix Reversals

18 Completeness and Compactness of First-Order Tableaux

Transcription:

To wards Empirical and Scientific Theories of Computation (Extended Abstract) Steven Meyer Pragmatic C Software Corp., Minneapolis, MN, USA smeyer@tdl.com Abstract The current situation in empirical testing of computational theories is considered. First, the development of computational thinking as logic and set theory in the late 19th and early 20th centuries is discussed. Next, current computer science research programmes are described. The paper continues with a discussion of the alternative empirical research programme in the study of mathematics and computation. Finally, two possible antinomies in current computer science are described and the out of favor Finslerian empirical set theory method from the 1920s is discussed to show alternative ways of thinking about and testing computational theories. 1. Late 19th and Early 20th Century Computational Thinking Computational and algorithmic study goes back at least to the 19th century. The study began with attempts to put the foundation of every day mathematics especially the use of infinity and real numbers on a sounder footing. This development occurred during a period in which mathematical formalism and structuralism were becoming the primary mathematical methodology. Mathematical objects are generated and existence is shown by recursive generation from axioms(chandler[1982] and Kunen[2009]). This formalist research programme was seen as formalizing all thinking until Russell s paradox was discovered in the beginning of the 20th century. The problem was solved in mathematics by adoption of the Zermelo-Frankel set theory axioms (ZFC) in the beginning of the 20th century (Kunen[2009], 4-8). This "Standard Model" in which sets are everything allowed mathematicians to continue to work on problems without worrying too much about methodological foundations. 2. Computational Thinking After the Beginning of Computer Science When computer science developed in the second half of the twentieth century, a number of factors combined to eliminate empiricism. 20th century logic and set theory replaced extensional (by listing and enumeration) descriptions by intensional (propositions stating what is desired) formulas and language. Because 19th century mathematics lacked computers, intensional descriptions of numbers and sets made sense because large numbers were not accessible (to calculation?), and it was felt proofs were needed to insure nothing different happened. Unfortunately, intensional descriptions led to antinomies (this Finsler[1996] term is used here instead of the possibly more common "paradox"). Meaning of statements such as The set of all x such xisirrational still pose

-2- complications for mathematical foundations. Computational thinking has dealt with such antinomies by turning a blind eye. Now 50 years after the first computers were constructed, large numbers are accessible, but extensional descriptions are still out of favor. Large but unbounded problems called potential infinity in the 19th century (Goldrei[1998], 66-73) has become infinity by unconscious problem solving. This situation can be seen in the dominant research programmes in the following computer science areas. 2.1 Computer Program Development In the area of algorithm implementation and computer programming, empiricism was barred by formalism as only computer programme proofs could show program correctness. Edsger Dijkstra s reply to criticism that proofs of computer programme correctness was different from mathematical proofs in a paper by Demillo et. al. (Demillo[1982], also cf. my empirical criticism in Meyer[1983])). The paper s title was "A Political Pamphlet from the Middle Ages". Dijkstra wrote "Besides political, the paper is pre-scientific in the sense that even the shallowest analogy is accepted as justification." (Dijkstra[2006]). 2.2 Artificial Intelligence In the area that studied the potential and the limits of computation, the artificial intelligence research programme became dominant and actively attempted to prevent competing research programme s from even receiving funding (see Lighthill[1972]). The research programme claimed that it was only a matter of time before computers surpassed humans. Since AI requires performance of logical reasoning better than human mathematicians, no empirical testing of Church s Thesis occurred (Kunen, 198-202). 2.3 Concrete Algorithm Efficiency In the area of concrete algorithm efficiency analysis, algorithm discovery by efficiency proof analysis became the dominant methodology (see Lakatos[1976] for a discussion of the mathematical method based on analysis of proofs). This method used mathematical methods so no empirical testing of foundation questions could occur, and algorithms created by human ingenuity not amenable to combinatoric proof were by definition impossible. 2.4 NP Completeness as Turing Machine Algorithm Efficiency The dominant research programme has tied foundation problems in effective computability to the efficiency ofnon deterministic Turing Machines. The antinomies that bothered 19th and early 20th Century mathematical have been eliminated by convention. Mathematical logic and ZFC became the "standard model" because of the elimination of efficiency models other than P=NP and because of the acceptance of Tarski s satisfiability definition of truth (for criticism see Finsler[1976], 162, "the distinction between true and false [must] be made in an objective [non axiomatic] way"). The idea behind NP completeness is that Church s thesis is useless if computations take more steps than the number of seconds the universe has existed. Since the P=NP problem is axiomatic in nature, no consideration of the alternative Kalmogorov complexity or possible antinomies in interpretation of problems proven tobenpcomplete is possible.

-3-3. Background of Empirical Testing in Computational Thinking There are two traditions which are in contrast to current formalist theories. Physicists have believed that one discovers mathematical truths from studying nature. For example J. Fourier has written "The deep study of nature is the most fruitful source of mathematical discoveries" (Moritz[1914], item 612). Lakatos mathematics as quasiempiricism documented the empiricist tradition without non foundational mathematics (Lakatos[1976] was widely accepted by set theorist and Logicians in the 1960s but was then rejected starting in the 1970s). Many mathematicians believe that mathematical concept are not merely conventionalist axioms but either exist or do not exist in the sense of images on Plato s cave wall. This view is called Platonism and implies that scientific testing and experiments can be used to determine the existence of mathematical theses such as the Church Turing Thesis which states that there is no possible computation outside recursively computable functions (Kunen[2009], 186-191). However, current formalist and ZFC set theorists have changed to meaning of Platonism to introspection (mathematical insight or deduction rather than induction from (possibly quasi-empirical) observation (Finsler[1996], p.6 introduction). 4. Two Antinomies In spite of almost no study, there are a few antinomies in computer science that I have run into in the area of computer program language compiler implementation. 1. Cooper s unexplained efficient flow graph algorithm There is an interesting graph theory area algorithm for computing (pre)dominators in computer language compiler flow graphs (Cooper[2001]) that appears to be faster than an algorithm proven to be optimal using algorithm efficiency proof analysis based combinatorics (Tarjan[1974]). If this algorithm is really outside mathematical efficiency provability, it may lead to the discovery of many new more efficient intuitive algorithms. 2. Computer instruction span dependent jump instruction selection The problem of selecting optimal assembler jump instructions was proven tobenpcomplete (Symanzki[1978] and the later [Leverett[1980]). Older computers had two types of jump instructions. One type was a fast and small instruction used if a jump was to a near memory address, and another larger and slower instruction for the general case. Programs are smaller if more local jump instructions are used, but if longer span jump instructions are required, if one wrong instruction is selected, it may cause many short span jump instructions to be eliminated. The history of this is interesting. The first paper "proves" NP completeness and suggested simplified algorithms that run in polynomial time. The second version, substitutes algorithm change with problem change. My claim here is that the general case problem and NP completeness proof show anantinomie because span instruction selection is not NP complete for programs that have meaning in a rather weak consistency ofthe meaning of computer program execution sense.

-4-5. The Finslerian Scientific Revolution Applied to Church s Thesis The 20th century Swiss mathematician Paul Finsler developed a detailed Platonistic and empirical alternative to ZFC. Finsler s "revolution" was not accepted (Gillies[1992], essay by Breger H. "A restoration that failed: Paul Finsler s theory of sets", 249-264). However, Finsler provides an alternative research program that may be usable in testing Church s theses and other modern computer science research programmes. Finsler s research programme is especially interesting because he published detailed answers to his critics including detailed re-proofs of his opponents disproofs of his solutions to various antinomies. The remainder of this talk analyzes Finsler s conception of truth and mathematics outside formalist finite Church/Turing computability. The aim of this talk is to encourage future computation thought that will allow various competing computational research programs to flourish, compete, and be used to test each other. 6. References Chandler[1982] Chandler, B. and Magnus, W. The History of Combinatorial Group Theory: A case Study in the History of Ideas, Springer, New York, 1982. Cook[1971] Cook, S. "The Complexity of Theorem-proving procedures," Proceedings of the third Annual ACM symposium on Theory of Computing., May, 1971, 151-158. Cooper[2001] Cooper, K, et. al. "A Simple, Fast Dominance Algorithm", Softw. DeMillo[1979] Pract. Expr. 4(2001), 1-10. De Millo, R. A., Lipton, R. J., and Perlis, A. J. Social processes and proofs of theorems and programs. CACM. 22, 5(1979), 271-280. Dijkstra[2006] Dijkstra, E. Dijkstra Archive (URL: http://userweb.cs.utexas.edu/users/ewd), University of Texas, 2008. Finsler[1996] Finsler, P.(Booth, D. and Ziegler, R. eds.) Finsler set theory: Platonism and Circularity. Birkhauser, 1996. Gillies[1982] Gillies, D. A. Frege, Dedekind, and Peano on the Foundations of Arithmetic. VanGorcum, Assen, Netherlands, 1982. Gillies[1992] Gillies, D. (ed.) Revolutions in Mathematics.. Oxford, 1992. Goldrei[1998] Goldrei, D. Classic Set Theory For Guided Independent Study. CRC Press, Florida, 1996. Kunen[2009] Kunen, K. The Foundations of Mathematics., Studies in Logic Vol. 19, College Publications, London, 2009. Lakatos[1976] Lakatos, I. Proofs and Refutations., Cambridge, 1976. Leverett[1980] Lighthill[1972] Leverett, B. and Szymanski, T. "Chaining Span Dependent Jump Instructions", ACM Trans Lang. and Sys. (TOPLAS), 3, 2(1980), 274-289. Lighthill, J, "Lighthill Report - Artificial Intelligence a General Survey" British Science Research Council (original report with

-5- responses available at www.tdl.com/~smeyer), 1972. Meyer[1983] Meyer, S. Pragmatic Versus Structured Computer Programming., Unpublished (www.tdl.com/~smeyer/docs/structprogbook- IntendedThesis.pdf), 1983. Moritz[1914] Moritz, R. On Mathematics and Mathematicians, Dover, New York, 1914. Szymanski[1978] Szymanski, T. "Assembling Code for machines with spandependent instructions", CACM. 21, 4(1978), 300-308. Tarjan[1974] Tarjan, R. "Finding Dominators in Directed Graphs", SIAM J. Comput., 3(1):62-89, March, 1974.