GAME THEORY, COMPLEXITY AND SIMPLICITY

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "GAME THEORY, COMPLEXITY AND SIMPLICITY"

Transcription

1 1 July 8, 1997 GAME THEORY, COMPLEXITY AND SIMPLICITY Part I: A Tutorial The theory of games is now over 50 years old. Its applications and misapplications abound. It is now "respectable". Bright young economic theorists bucking for promotion need to be aware of agency theory, reputation theory, the new industrial organization, auction theory, refinements of equilibria, perfect equilibria, trembling hand equilibria, strong equilibria, Bayesian equilibria, problems with common knowledge and to be aware of game theoretic applications to biology, political science, law and even anthropology. The public is aware of phrases such as the "zero sum game". Many individuals who know next to no game theory have heard of the "Prisoners' Dilemma". The word "strategy" has been given a scientific twist. Newspaper columnists are already using or misusing the terminology. All in all, game theory has arrived. This note is divided into three parts aimed at being a tutorial, retrospective essay and critique. The tutorial is called for to help inform those who are uninformed. Possibly even more important, it aims to help inform those who are misinformed and may be somewhat misled by the academic fashion show. In particular the noncooperative equilibrium is explained and the use and limitations of its applications are discussed. The meaning of cooperative game theory is explained and its uses and limitations are noted. The reasons for the gross inadequacy of a dynamic theory of games are noted and the need for a considerably different approach is suggested 1 The key to understanding the uses and limitations of game theory is to appreciate that the game theoretic approaches are not monolithic and depending on which one the individual follows the world view obtained is highly different. In particular the four most important distinctions are: 1 Those who wish to delve further into details will find the three volume handbook editied by Aumann and Hart (1992, 1994 and 1997 forthcoming) to be of considerable assistance.

2 2 1. Game theory as mathematics; 2. Game theory as science; 3. Game theory as philosophy; 4. Game theory as advocacy. Some brief observations are made here on these distinctions. They will be expanded further in a subsequent note. After these are discussed, some basic exposition is given. 1. Game theory as mathematics Prior to the theory of games the prime emphasis in mathematical techniques applied to economics was to differential calculus, differential and difference equations. Combinatorics was hardly considered. The stress in von Neumann and Morgenstern was on choices among finite sets 2. Not only did they stress finite combinatorics in individual choice. They then proceeded to develop a combinatoric theory of cooperative social choice where the stress was on the powers of all coalitions which could be formed among the players. In their development of the theory of the two-person zero sum game the stress was on finite choices and how to calculate optimal strategies. The method of calculation called for was, in essence, linear programming. There are many purely mathematical problems which are posed in game theoretic investigations and it is possible to regard oneself as a game theorist with no empirical concerns whatsoever, limiting oneself to the new mathematical problems which are posed by the game theory models. 2. Game theory as science It was the original intention of von Neumann and Morgenstern to apply game theory to problems in economics. However the range of scientific applications has been far broader, including all of the social sciences as well as biology. It has also served to provide the underlying structure for experimental gaming, providing the models which help to show the limits of individual rational behavior. The scientific applications can be split into pure and applied. Examples of pure science based on game theory would be the gaming investigations of O'Neill (1987), Roth (1987) and others (see Shubik, 1987 for a survey) and the current work in evolutionary game theory and biology. ( See Weibull, 1996 for a survey.) Game theory as applied science and operation research has been used in voting design (see Shapley and Shubik 1954 and Banzhaf 1965); in designing auction mechanisms, in setting aircraft landing fees in deciding on the assignment of overhead costs (Shubik, 1962) and utilized by the military in weapons design. 2 These could be huge sets, such as the set of strategies in chess. The contemplation of the size of such sets has raised problems concerning how individuals explore large numbers of alternatives.

3 3 3. Game theory as philosophy Von Neumann and Morgenstern placed extremely stringent conditions on their description of a game. It was assumed that all players were completely informed about all of the rules, including each other's preferences and assets. Deep philosophical problems are posed if the assumption of common knowledge is abandoned. One has to deal with assumptions about A s knowledge of what B knows and B s knowledge of what A knows about B and so forth, in an infinite regression. There is a virutual subindustry in Game Theory dealing with how to treat lack of common knowledge (see Aumann, 1976). Von Neumann and Morgenstern, in their investigation of non-zero sum games showed that the ordinary concept of individual rational behavior did not generalize in a unique natural simple way as soon as there is more than one than one individual in a nonzero sum game. Harsanyi and Selten (1988) have proposed the existence of a unique noncooperative equilibrium as the normative solution to a game; others have argued that the various normative features one might require for a solution (such as symmetry, efficiency and equity) may be in conflict. The meaning of rational behavior in an n-person game, even with common knowledge is still open to debate. Furthermore both a normative and descriptive viewpoint to game theoretic solutions are supported with differing emphasis by the professional game theorists. It can be argued that one should play in a twoperson zero sum game according to the Minimax strategy and a strong case can be made that the concept of the individual rational decision-maker extends to zero sum games. There is no consensus as to what constitutes the right solution for nonconstant sum games. 4. Game theory as advocacy With the growth of the acceptance of game theoretic concepts and ways of formulating the analysis of public problems such as national defense or regulation of industrial organization the use of game theory as metaphor has grown. Possibly the earliest examples are given in the works of Schelling (1960), Ellsberg (1956) and Rapoport (1960). Game theoretic thought mixed in with psychology, social psychology and international relations flavored the works of Wohlstetter (1975) and Herman Kahn (1960). I term this type of use as conversational game theory. This is not meant to be a pejorative term. The use of conversational game theoretic argument as portrayed by the writings noted above probably had considerable influence on nuclear deterrence policy and cold war strategy. Von Neumann s stress was on cooperative game theory and he was adamantly opposed to one point solutions, i.e., to using game theory for specific prediction. Thus it is unlikely that his strong views on defense were based on his game theoretic thought.

4 4 Von Neumann & Morgenstern's great book The seminal book in game theory was published in It is large, innovative and impressive. But it is such that very few individuals appear to have read it in toto. A reason why many individuals have read some parts of Game Theory and Economic Behavior, but few have read it all the way through is because it may be regarded as four books in one. It deals with four topics all of which can be treated independently. They are: 1. Preferences and utility theory. 2. The extensive form of a game. 3. The description of, and solution to a 2-person zero sum game 4. The description of, and stable set solution to an n person non-zero sum game played cooperatively. Preferences and utility theory In their need to define precisely the goal of each player, von Neumann and Morgenstern built upon the usual (highly approximate) assumptions of microeconomic theory that individuals have completely ordered preferences. By providing an axiomatic treatment of preferences including axioms on risk behavior they were able to show that preferences could be represented by a utility function completely specified up to a linear transformation. This result, which von Neumann and Morgenstern needed in order to set up and study the two person zero sum game was the founding seminal contribution to the abstract treatment of the study of many different types of preference structure. Their work led to the investigation of problems concerning individual ability to develop a complete ordering of preferences for items among which they have to choose, and individual ability to gauge risk preferences. It also raised questions concerning the possibility for interpersonal comparison of welfare; and how closely efficient transfer of utility can be achieved by the availability of a money like commodity to be used as a means for making side payments. The formal axiomatic approach of von Neumann and Morgenstern to the measurement of utility led to the investigation of many other preference structures, such as partially ordered preferences. The extensive form of a game. Until the development of the theory of games a language and notation to describe a formal structure for conscious decision making had hardly been developed. The extensive form of game delineated by a game tree (in a one person version it is referred to as a decision tree) provided a means to make precise the concepts of move, choice, information strategy, play, outcome and payoff. The authors choice of the title theory of games was based on utilizing their insights into the formal structure of games such as chess, Go, or Bridge. Figure 1 shows a game tree for a

5 two person game where Player (or decision maker) 1 chooses his move first among three possible moves. Player 2 is informed if Player 1 selects his first move, but is not fully informed if the choice of Player 1 is move 2 or 3. Player 2 then makes his choice. He has to choose between two moves. The game reaches a terminal node of the tree. At each terminal node there is an outcome. Each player assigns a value or utility to the outcome. For example The game tree Figure 1 in chess an outcome at a terminal point in the tree might be that Black checkmates White. Black evaluates this outcome at a value of 1 and White evaluates it at 0. In Figure 1 the nodes of the tree (except the terminal nodes) represent choice points. They are points at which some player must select a move. The branches emanating from each choice point are the moves. They are numbered so that they can be identified. The choice points are circled by a closed curve which may contain one or more points. These curves are information sets. Each information set is labeled with the name of the player to whom it belongs. In Figure 1 Player 2 has two information sets labeled by P 2. The left information set contains a single point. This indicates that if the game proceeds to that node, when Player 2 is called upon to move he knows exactly where he is. This contrasts with the information set on the right. If Player 1 had selected either his second or third moves, when Player 2 is called upon to move he does not know which move Player 1 has selected. If Player 2 selects his first move because of his lack of information he does not know which one of the two possible outcomes will emerge. An information set could be more descriptively called a lack of information set as it describes the level of ignorance of the player. The initial node of the game tree bears the additional label of O which indicates where the game starts. The terminal nodes in Figure 1 are labeled with the outcomes win, draw or lose. Underneath the label at each terminal two numbers appear. The first is the value attached to the outcome by Player 1 and the second, the value attached to the outcome by Player 2. Given this language we can now describe the basic features of any game. A path down the game tree starting from the initial node and ending at some terminal node describes a play of the game. It is a more general form of the type of description of a chess game reported in the newspapers. It indicates where the game began and indicates the selection of moves by each of the players down to the final outcome. The numbers at the terminal nodes indicate the payoffs or the worth of the final outcome to each player. In theory, with this notation we could draw a full game tree for a game such as chess. But a little contemplation of that game is sufficient to indicate that we would exhaust the world s paper supply if we tried to draw this game tree on the same scale as Figure 1. 5

6 6 The notation developed for the description of the game theory enables us to give a precise comprehensive definition of the meaning of strategy. A strategy is an all encompassing plan which contains instructions concerning what a player should do under all contingencies. It can be easily understood and illustrated by considering the game shown in Figure 1 and displaying a few strategies. Player 1 has three strategies which coincide with his moves. This coincidence occurs because he has no contingencies for which he has to plan. Suppose Player 1 were going out of town before he was due to play and that he wanted to leave a complete book of instructions for the individual who was going to play for him. He could leave any one of three extremely simple books of instructions. The first book of instructions would simply say: Select move 1. This is somewhat unimpressive, but matters change when we suppose that it is Player 2 who is out of town and he is leaving instructions to someone who is going to play for him. One such book of instructions is of the following form: If Player 1 selects move 1 select 1; if he selects moves 2 or 3 then select 2. We could abbreviate this description to (1,2). A little work shows that there are four different books of instruction which could have been left by Player 2. They are (1,2), (2,2), (1,1) or (2,1). Thus in this game Player 1 has three strategies and Player 2 has 4. Rather than analyze the game in extensive form we can obliterate the details of description in terms of the game tree complete with details concerning information and replace it with a matrix which illustrates the interaction between all of the strategies of one player and all of the strategies of the other. P 2 (1,2) (2,2) (1,1) (2,1) 1 1,0 1/2,1/2 1,0 1/2,1/2 2 1,0 0,1 0,1 1,0 3 0,1 1,0 1,0 0,1 Table 1 A simple example shows how the entries in the cells are calculated. Suppose that Player 1 selects his first strategy and player 2 selects his strategy denoted by (2,2). This tells us that Player 2 s reply is to select move 2 for the payoffs of (1/2, 1/2).

7 7 The description of, and solution to a 2-person zero sum game A zero sum game is a game in which the interests of the players are diametrically opposed. What one player wins, the other loses 3. Chess, Go and Checkers provide examples of two person zero sum games. A five person Poker game is a five person zero sum game. Von Neumann and Morgenstern devised a special theory to analyze two person zero sum games. In order to do so they made use of the strategic form of a game They confined their interest to a game description only in terms of strategies and payoffs. The detail provided by the extensive form is suppressed. Thus there are many game trees or games in extensive form which give rise to the same game in extensive form. A great loss of detailed information has taken place in going to the strategic form. The sort of structure on which one might wish to base an analysis of dynamics has been replaced by a structure better suited to study equilibrium and statics. A simple example serves to illustrate the relationship between the extensive form and the strategic form. Figure 2a and b show a game in which both Player 1 and 2 each must select between two moves in complete ignorance of the other s actions. The only difference between the two game trees are that in Figure 2a Player 1 moves first; in 2b Player 2 moves first. As it is assumed that neither player has the opportunity to peek, the games are strategically equivalent. For each player in this simple game a strategy and a move are equivalent. Each must select move one or two. Figures 2a,b The strategic form representation of the game is given in Table 2. Player 1 selects a row and Player 2 selects a column. The first number in each cell represents the payoff to Player 1 and the second number, the payoff to Player 2. Thus, for example. if Player 1 uses his second strategy and Player 2 his first, Player 1 loses 10 and Player 2 gains 10. If Player 1 selects his first P ,-5 0,0 2-10,10 5,-5 Table 2 3 More generally rather than zero sum we could talk of constant sum games where an arbitrary constant (say a gift from Uncle Harry) is added to each of the payoffs to a player. Third part of his payoff is independent of the strategies employed (See Shubik, 1982 Ch 8)

8 8 move with a probability of 3/4 and his second move with a probability of 1/4 he can guarantee that no matter what Player 2 does his expected gain will be 5/4. This illustrates the Maxmin solution for a two person zero sum game. The Row player can guarantee that his expectation is no less than a certain amount and the column player can prevent the row player from obtaining more than this amount by selecting his first move with a probability of 1/4 and his second move with probability of 3/4. Here we note that the players do not select a single row or column with certainty, but select both rows or columns with a calculated probability for each row or column. Such a strategy is referred to as a mixed strategy. Player 1 is guaranteed his maxmin. The Maxmin solution suggested by von Neumann for the two person zero sum game can be regarded as a normative solution. If the player wishes to maximize his expected gain he should use his maxmin strategy. Except for parlor games and some military problems there are few actual situations which model as pure zero sum games. Experimental evidence on actual performance of players playing a 2 x 2 or a 3 x 3 matrix game is mixed. When the matrix is bigger than 3 x 3 players display information processing and computational limitations. Solutions to an n person non-zero sum game played cooperatively. Von Neumann and Morgenstern developed three different representations of a game of strategy. They are: 1. The extensive form; 2. The strategic form and 3. The cooperative or coalitional form The extensive form can be utilized to provide a complete process description of the game. We discuss the extensive form below after considering the noncooperative equilibrium solution. The strategic form, as illustrated above serves to enable us to analyze the game in terms of strategies. The characteristic function or coalitional form provides a basis from which the combinatorics of potential collaboration can be studied. Table 3 shows a simple 2 x 2 nonconstant sum game in matrix form 4. If each player uses his first strategy each obtains a payoff of 5. If Player 1 uses his first strategy and Player 2 uses his second strategy, Player 1 obtains -10 and Player 2 obtains 15. If both use their second strategy each obtains 0. It is easy to observe that jointly, by cooperating, each using their first strategy, the players could obtain 10 together. 4 More accurately, in bimatrix form as there are two entries in each cell.

9 9 P , 5-10, , -10 0, 0 Table 3 Each player acting independently cannot guarantee for himself more than 0. The characteristic function of a game with n players illustrates the amounts that any of the 2 n coalitions can obtain if the members of the coalition cooperate 5. For the simple game illustrated in strategic form in Table 3 the characteristic function is as is shown in Table 4. v({1}) = 0, v({2}) = 0 v({1,2}) = 10 Table 4 The reason why we use a double set of brackets around the numbers is to indicate that for example v({1}) stands for the value of the coalition consisting of the set containing only Player 1. The curly brackets {} indicate a set. The coalition consisting either of Player 1 or 2 cannot guarantee more than zero. The coalition of both 1 and 2 together can obtain 10. If one is presented with just the characteristic function of the game, the details concerning the strategic structure for individual are suppressed. A way of looking at the information conveyed by the characteristic function is that it at the level of aggregation designed for a diplomat or negotiator. It tells him nothing about the strategic choices facing the generals only the values of coalitions. The extensive form is better designed for use of individuals concerned with the details of information and moves. Bits of it must be considered by those concerned with tactics and the specifics of play rather than with overall strategy. Figure 5 illustrates a three person game in characteristic function form. It tells us that Player 3 is more desirable than 1 or 2 in any two person coalition and that Player 2 is more desirable than 1. Here we have not bothered to illustrate either the extensive or strategic forms which would give rise to this characteristic function. There are many different games which would produce this characteristic function; but if we are only interested in the sort of negotiations which 5 For formal mathematical rigor one usually attaches a value of zero to the coalition consisting of nobody.

10 would have the three players decide on how to split the four units they can earn by cooperation we do not need the other detail. v({1}) = v({2}) = v({3}) = 0 v({1,2}) = 1, v({1,3}) = 2, v({2,3}) = 3 v({1,2,3}) = Figure 5 Von Neumann and Morgenstern defined an imputation to be a vector of n numbers whose sum adds up to the amount that the group as a whole could obtain by cooperation. Referring to Table 5 the vector (.9, 1.2, 1.9) is an imputation. It says that Player 1 receives.9; Player 2 receives 1.2 and Player 3 receives 1.9. These three numbers add to 4 which is the amount that the coalition of all could obtain. The key operation they considered was that of domination. An imputation is said to dominate and imputation if some set of players which we call S are better off in than in and by going into business for themselves they could obtain at least as much as. Rather than leave us with an abstract exercise using Greek letters a simple example utilizing the game illustrated in Figure 5 can make this concept clear. Suppose that the imputation were (1, 2, 1) and were (.8, 2.3,.9) then dominates via the set S={1,3} because Players 1 and 3 acting together without Player 2 can obtain 2 thus they have the power to select over. The theory of n-person games developed by von Neumann and Morgenstern was both static and cooperative. The authors were at pains to stress that they regarded the development of a useful dynamics as beyond their scope. They indicated however that much of value could be constructed by concentrating on the statics. Their approach towards the many person problem was in part normative and in part positive in the sense that they felt that the society as a whole should try to make the cake as big as possible, but that groups would bargain and negotiate over their shares of the cake. There are four solution concepts of note which have been developed and applied to cooperative games represented by a characteristic function. They are the stable set solution proposed by von Neumann and Morgenstern and the solutions known as the core, the value and the nucleolus of an n-person game. Without going into mathematical detail it is not possible to do full justice to the specific structure of each of these solutions. However given the concepts of imputation and domination, some intuitive insights can be provided concerning the basic concepts underlying each of the solutions.

11 11 The stable set solution The stable set solution reflects the possibility for the distribution of resources to depend on a variety of complex social structures. The stress is on extreme nonuniqueness of outcomes. In essence, a stable set solution cannot be used to make a unique prediction, all that it does is to delineate a subset of the outcomes. Many imputations of wealth may make up a single solution. When all of the imputations in a solution are considered together it is the relationship between all of them that imposes a social stability on the whole. 6 There can be many different stable sets rewarding different groups considerably different gains which are all nevertheless consistent with the same resource structure The core. The core of an n-person is the set of imputations which are undominated, i.e the set of ways of dividing the overall pie in a manner such that no group could do better if it tried to go into business for itself. Referring to the game illustrated in Table 5 the imputation (.5, 1, 2.5) is in the core as there is no coalition whose members can all do better by themselves. The core can be viewed as the set of outcomes impervious to countervailing power. It reflects a stability against all coalitions. It can be proved that the competitive price system of an economy lies in the core ( for discussion and references see Shubik, 1984). The value The value solution to an n-person game is a solution devised by Shapley (1953) which evaluates an a priori worth of each individual to the overall game. In essence, it averages over the marginal contribution that each individual makes to all the coalitions into which he could enter. A special example of a four person game may help to illustrate the nature of the value solution. We may consider a special type of game which is represented by an extremely simple chartacteristic function. It is called a simple game because all of the payoffs obtained by the coalitions are either 0 or 1. A coalition with a joint payoff of 0 is called a losing coalition. A coalition with joint payoff of 1 is called a losing coalition. The simple game can be used to study the intrinsic assignment of power in a voting structure as a function of the number of votes controlled by each individual. Suppose that there is a corporation with 4 stockholders. The first stockholder has 2 votes and the other three stockholders have 1 vote each. There is a way in which we can assign an a priori value or measure of power to each stockholder. Suppose that instead of there being four stockholders with five shares split among them, there had been five stockholders, each with one share, a reasonable assignment of power among the five stockholders would be.2 to each of them. 6 The technical statement is that a solution consists of a set of imputations which do not dominate each other but dominate all other imputations.

12 Each is equally relevant in being able to turn a losing coalition into a winning coalition. But suppose that there were only three voters with the stock distributed as (3,1,1). If the vote is settled by a simple majority of the stock held then it evident that the stockholder with 3 shares holds all of the power and those with 1 share each hold none of the power 7. This elementary exercise tells us that as an individual's holding of shares increases his power must change in a nonlinear manner. Once he has more than half of the shares he has all of the power. The value calculation counts all of the marginal contributions that an individual makes to every coalition and averages over them. When the game is large and has little special structure this calculation is long and messy. In games representing voting situations where there are only winning and losing coalitions 8 the marginal contribution of a player is either 0 or 1. It is 0 when he joins a losing coalition and it remains losing, or when he joins a winning coalition and it remains winning. 9 It is 1 when the addition of the player changes a losing coalition into a winning coalition. We may imagine coalition formation taking place in every possible order. Call the players A, B, C and D where A has 2 votes and the others 1 each. There are 24 ways the individuals could line up. These are shown below. Starting with the player at the left we can consider a coalition growing as each player is added. Credit is given to the pivotal player who coverts a losing coalition into a winning coalition. This is illustrated by a * next to the pivotal player. AB*CD, AB*DC, AC*BD, AC*DB, AD*BC, AD* CB BA*CD, BA*DC, CA*BD, CA*DB, DA*BC, DA*CB BCA*D, CBA*D, DCA*B, CDA*B, BDA*C, DBA*C BCD*A, BDC*A, CBD*A, CDB*,A DBC*A, DCB*A. We note that in the 24 possibilities A is pivotal 12 times and B, C and D are pivotal 4 times each. The a priori division of power among the voters is (1/2, 1/6, 1/6, 1/6). The phrase a priori is used to indicate that this measure is free of any of the sociological structure that might be present in the set of players. All way in which coalitions might be formed are regarded as equiprobable. In an actual society there may be nets of friends or others whose interests are correlated who act together In actuality there is a body of law which protects minority stockholders against the complete power of the majority, but for this example we assume that "winner can take all". 8 Ties must also be accounted for, but here for ease in illustration we consider a voting game with an odd number of votes where all vote and hence there are no ties. 9 In actual political practice although a minimal winning coalition is desirable as there are fewer participants to share the payoff, a few extra players may be of worth in order to insure against accidental failure to be present at the vote.

13 13 The nucleolus The nucleolus is a solution concept devised by Schmeidler (1969) which seeks to find an imputation or a means of dividing the cake in such a manner that the maximum complaint by any coalition against the division is minimized. It may be regarded as a sophisticated version of a splitthe-difference approach to fair division. If the game being studied has a core then the nucleolus is the centroid of the core. The Cournot-Nash Noncooperative Equilibrium In contrast with the cooperative, normative game solution approach noted above Augustin Cournot (1838) suggested a solution to two firms in competition in a market which involved each taking the others expected strategic behavior into account. He showed that there would be a noncooperative equilibrium point which had the property that there would exist a pair of expectations such that if each had the appropriate expectation and based his action on this expectation then the resultant out come would be self-fulfilling, i.e. the expectation of each would turn out to be true. John Nash [20] provided the general definition and proof of the existence of the noncooperative equilibrium. Referring to the simple matrix game shown in Table 3 (known as the Prisoner s Dilemma game) we can see that if Player 2 expected Player 1 to use his second strategy then Player 1's optimal response would be to use his second strategy and viceversa. Thus the pair of strategies (2,2) would be in equilibrium and would result in a pair of payoffs of (0,0). In contrast if both had selected their first strategy and acted cooperatively they would have obtained payoffs of (5,5). The noncooperative equilibrium solution has also been applied to games in extensive form. Unfortunately when such an attempt is made a host of new problems occur which can be more or less ascribed to the unsatisfactory relationship between statics and dynamics. The equilibrium analysis is essentially static and for it to hold in a game with many stages one approach has been to consider a backward induction where the presumption is that at every point in the game the expectations of the players guide them to an equilibrium. The mathematical formulation and proof of existence of at least one, and often, many noncooperative equilibria tells us little about the dynamics encountered in a game where the players start to play at a position away from equilibrium. In essence, the noncooperative equilibrium solution points out the existence of outcomes which satisfy a condition on the consistency of everyone's expectations. Although there is some experimental evidence that the noncooperative equilibrium serves as a reasonable approximation to long term behavior in some games with many players and a single noncooperative equilibrium point, little is known with any generality about actual behavior. The noncooperative equilibrium solution should not be regarded as a normative solution as, in general, jointly optimal outcomes

14 may not be achieved. Further discussion and a critique of the problems encountered in utilizing the noncooperative equilibrium solution will be given in Part II. 14 Dynamics and the infinite horizon The game theory models presented above have a definite beginning and end. The initial conditions in the instance of a game of chess are given precisely by the placing of the pieces on an 8 x 8 board. The end is well defined by the rules including conventions to prevent endless cycling so that the game is finite. When we try to model most human activities the initial position reflects history and the social context which sets the stage for individual action. Unlike a game of chess, much of human behavior depends in an important way on history from an unbounded past and expectations concerning an unbounded future. When formal game models are constructed to reflect ongoing games, the distinction between cooperative and noncooperative solutions becomes blurred. As there is always the possibility of a tomorrow, the opportunity to punish doublecrossers and to specify threats which can be used to enforce cooperation becomes a reality. Structure and Behavior A brief review of the formalization and different types of representation of a game of strategy has been presented, followed by an exposition of different solution concepts. The stress has been on the development of a language to describe conscious individual decision making in situations involving one or more individuals with well-defined goals and ability to calculate. Von Neumann and Morgenstern provided a seminal idea in devising a means to describe the full structure of a game, such as chess. In human society there are games within games. Although a particular game, in the short run, may take place in a specific context, the actions of the individuals, may in the long run, influence the environment in which they behave. This type of feedback is not represented in the formulations presented here. The provision of a way to make precise "the rules of the game" and to describe in careful detail the set of all possible ways a game might be played does not provide us with a prescription as to how the game should be played, nor with the evidence as to how the game is actually played by humans. Game theorists have approached the problems involving human motivation and behavior by suggesting a mathematical description of individual preferences, attrbiuting individual optimization as the motivation and devising normative or other solution concepts to account for the interactions of many individuals all in pursuit of their own welfare. Each of the five solution concepts suggested has attractive features. The four cooperative solutions are explicit in indicating the different norms they fulfill and useful applications have been found for the value, core and nucleolus. The noncooperative equilibrium solution is justified more for descriptive reasons and fits into the spirit of recent finance and price system economics where the idea of the

15 15 noncooperative equilibrium is translated into rational expectations. It has also been applied to biology with a somewhat different interpretation of the concept of a mixed strategy equilibrium. In the subsequent discussion, it is suggested that the influence of game theory has been substantial and the applications at several levels have been of great value; but its very success has served to highlight the limitations of the rationalistic models of economic man in coming to grips with the many socio-economic and politico-economic problems which are faced by any large society. The game theoretic language has provided a means to build process models in which the institutions and other aspects of the environment are the carriers of process. These are implicit in the rules of the game 9. The game theoretic solutions are of considerable power in studying some problems of interest, but as models of human behavior, they are lacking and the basic apparatus of game theory drives us to abandon the model of the decision maker as completely informed about the rules of the game with common knowledge about what all others know or do not know. The precision and analytical power of game theory forces us to understand the model of utilitarian man and its direct descendent homo oeconomicus instead of being an idealization of purposeful human decision makers are poor approximations to the far more complicated perception and computationaly-limited human being driven by passions, in part ruled by habit and in part controlled by instinct, whose decisions are set in the context of the society he or she belongs to. The mathematical analysis underlying much of game theory and economic theory was made feasible by the gross simplification of the model of the individual. This may have been fine for some of the original purposes at hand. With the advent of the computer and the possibilities of computation and simulation, the stage is set to enrich the study of models of human behavior using the framework provided by game theory as a starting point from which we may investigate multiperson interaction.

16 16 REFERENCES Aumann, R.J Agreeing to disagree. Annals of Statistics. 4: Aumann, R. J. and S. Hart (eds) 1992, 1994, Handbook of Game Theory, vols I and II and III forthcoming Banzhaf, J.F., Weighted voting doesn t work: A mathematical analysis. Rutgers Law Review 19: Ellsberg, D Theory of the Reluctant Duelist. American Economic Review 46: Harsanyi, J. and R. Selten, A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games Cambridge: M.I.T. Press. Kahn, H On Thermonuclear War Princeton: Princeton University Press. Luce, D. and H. Raiffa Games and Decisions Wiley: New York. Nash, J.F., Jr., "Noncooperative Games." Annals of Mathematics 54: Nash, J.F. Jr., "Equilibrium Points In N-Person Games." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA 36: O'Neill, B., 1987 Nonmetric tesat of the minimax thewory of two-person zerosum games, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, U.S.A., 84: Rapoport, A. 1960, Fights, Games and Debates Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Roth, A.E., Laboratory Experimentation in Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schelling, T., 1960 The Strategy of Conflict. Bambridge Mass. Harvard University Press. Schmeidler, D., "The Nucleolus Of A Characteristic Function Game." SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics 17 (6): Shapley, L.S., "A Value For N-Person Games". In Annals of Mathematical Studies, R.D. Luce and A.W. Tucker, eds. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp Shapley, L.S., 1975, "Cardinal Utility from Intensity Comparisons", RAND Corporation, Publication R-1683-PR. Shapley, L.S. & M. Shubik., 1954 A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System. American Political Science Review 48: Shapley, L.S. and Shubik, M., 1969a. "On the Core of an Economic System with Externalities," American Economic Review, 10: Shapley, L.S. and Shubik, M., 1969b. "Pure Competition, Coalitional Power and Fair Division," International Economic Review, 10:

17 Shubik, M "Incentives, Decentralized Control, The Assignment Of Joint Costs And Internal Pricing," Management Science, 8, 2: Shubik, M.., "Edgeworth Market Games," In Annals of Mathematical Studies, Volume 40, R.D. Luce and A.W. Tucker, eds., Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ, pp Shubik, M., 1959b. Strategy and Market Structure, New York: Wiley. Shubik, M., 1962, "Some Experimental Non Zero Games with Lack of Information about the Rules," Management Science, 8: Shubik, M., Game Theory in the Social Sciences, Vol. 1, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Shubik, M., Game Theory in the Social Sciences, Vol. 2: A Game Theoretic Approach to Political Economy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Shubik, M. "Game Theory and Experimental Gaming," To appear in Handbook of Game Theory, vol III R. J. Aumann and S. Hart (ed) forthcoming Von Neumann, J. and O. Morgenstern, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ. Weibull, J. W Evolutionary Game Theory Cambridge, Mass M.I.T Press. Wohlstetter, A Optimal Ways To Confuse Ourselves. Foreign Policy 20:

Game Theory: introduction and applications to computer networks

Game Theory: introduction and applications to computer networks Game Theory: introduction and applications to computer networks Lecture 1: introduction Giovanni Neglia INRIA EPI Maestro 30 January 2012 Part of the slides are based on a previous course with D. Figueiredo

More information

Distributed Optimization and Games

Distributed Optimization and Games Distributed Optimization and Games Introduction to Game Theory Giovanni Neglia INRIA EPI Maestro 18 January 2017 What is Game Theory About? Mathematical/Logical analysis of situations of conflict and cooperation

More information

Computational Aspects of Game Theory Bertinoro Spring School Lecture 2: Examples

Computational Aspects of Game Theory Bertinoro Spring School Lecture 2: Examples Computational Aspects of Game Theory Bertinoro Spring School 2011 Lecturer: Bruno Codenotti Lecture 2: Examples We will present some examples of games with a few players and a few strategies. Each example

More information

Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory. Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2016 Prof. Michael Kearns

Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory. Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2016 Prof. Michael Kearns Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2016 Prof. Michael Kearns Game Theory for Fun and Profit The Beauty Contest Game Write your name and an integer between 0 and 100 Let

More information

Distributed Optimization and Games

Distributed Optimization and Games Distributed Optimization and Games Introduction to Game Theory Giovanni Neglia INRIA EPI Maestro 18 January 2017 What is Game Theory About? Mathematical/Logical analysis of situations of conflict and cooperation

More information

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 4

Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 4 Microeconomics of Banking: Lecture 4 Prof. Ronaldo CARPIO Oct. 16, 2015 Administrative Stuff Homework 1 is due today at the end of class. I will upload the solutions and Homework 2 (due in two weeks) later

More information

CHAPTER LEARNING OUTCOMES. By the end of this section, students will be able to:

CHAPTER LEARNING OUTCOMES. By the end of this section, students will be able to: CHAPTER 4 4.1 LEARNING OUTCOMES By the end of this section, students will be able to: Understand what is meant by a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium (BNE) Calculate the BNE in a Cournot game with incomplete information

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 2: Backward induction and subgame perfection Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Microeconomics II Lecture 2: Backward induction and subgame perfection Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 Microeconomics II Lecture 2: Backward induction and subgame perfection Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 1 Games in extensive form So far, we have only considered games where players

More information

Game Theory: The Basics. Theory of Games and Economics Behavior John Von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (1943)

Game Theory: The Basics. Theory of Games and Economics Behavior John Von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (1943) Game Theory: The Basics The following is based on Games of Strategy, Dixit and Skeath, 1999. Topic 8 Game Theory Page 1 Theory of Games and Economics Behavior John Von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (1943)

More information

ECON 312: Games and Strategy 1. Industrial Organization Games and Strategy

ECON 312: Games and Strategy 1. Industrial Organization Games and Strategy ECON 312: Games and Strategy 1 Industrial Organization Games and Strategy A Game is a stylized model that depicts situation of strategic behavior, where the payoff for one agent depends on its own actions

More information

Copyright 2008, Yan Chen

Copyright 2008, Yan Chen Unless otherwise noted, the content of this course material is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution Non-Commercial 3.0 License. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/ Copyright 2008, Yan

More information

Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory. Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2014 Prof. Michael Kearns

Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory. Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2014 Prof. Michael Kearns Introduction to (Networked) Game Theory Networked Life NETS 112 Fall 2014 Prof. Michael Kearns percent who will actually attend 100% Attendance Dynamics: Concave equilibrium: 100% percent expected to attend

More information

Game Theory and Randomized Algorithms

Game Theory and Randomized Algorithms Game Theory and Randomized Algorithms Guy Aridor Game theory is a set of tools that allow us to understand how decisionmakers interact with each other. It has practical applications in economics, international

More information

Advanced Microeconomics: Game Theory

Advanced Microeconomics: Game Theory Advanced Microeconomics: Game Theory P. v. Mouche Wageningen University 2018 Outline 1 Motivation 2 Games in strategic form 3 Games in extensive form What is game theory? Traditional game theory deals

More information

Appendix A A Primer in Game Theory

Appendix A A Primer in Game Theory Appendix A A Primer in Game Theory This presentation of the main ideas and concepts of game theory required to understand the discussion in this book is intended for readers without previous exposure to

More information

THEORY: NASH EQUILIBRIUM

THEORY: NASH EQUILIBRIUM THEORY: NASH EQUILIBRIUM 1 The Story Prisoner s Dilemma Two prisoners held in separate rooms. Authorities offer a reduced sentence to each prisoner if he rats out his friend. If a prisoner is ratted out

More information

(a) Left Right (b) Left Right. Up Up 5-4. Row Down 0-5 Row Down 1 2. (c) B1 B2 (d) B1 B2 A1 4, 2-5, 6 A1 3, 2 0, 1

(a) Left Right (b) Left Right. Up Up 5-4. Row Down 0-5 Row Down 1 2. (c) B1 B2 (d) B1 B2 A1 4, 2-5, 6 A1 3, 2 0, 1 Economics 109 Practice Problems 2, Vincent Crawford, Spring 2002 In addition to these problems and those in Practice Problems 1 and the midterm, you may find the problems in Dixit and Skeath, Games of

More information

Exercises for Introduction to Game Theory SOLUTIONS

Exercises for Introduction to Game Theory SOLUTIONS Exercises for Introduction to Game Theory SOLUTIONS Heinrich H. Nax & Bary S. R. Pradelski March 19, 2018 Due: March 26, 2018 1 Cooperative game theory Exercise 1.1 Marginal contributions 1. If the value

More information

Introduction: What is Game Theory?

Introduction: What is Game Theory? Microeconomics I: Game Theory Introduction: What is Game Theory? (see Osborne, 2009, Sect 1.1) Dr. Michael Trost Department of Applied Microeconomics October 25, 2013 Dr. Michael Trost Microeconomics I:

More information

DECISION MAKING GAME THEORY

DECISION MAKING GAME THEORY DECISION MAKING GAME THEORY THE PROBLEM Two suspected felons are caught by the police and interrogated in separate rooms. Three cases were presented to them. THE PROBLEM CASE A: If only one of you confesses,

More information

Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior Chapter 1 and Chapter 2. Author: Siim Adamson TTÜ 2010

Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior Chapter 1 and Chapter 2. Author: Siim Adamson TTÜ 2010 Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior Chapter 1 and Chapter 2 review Author: Siim Adamson TTÜ 2010 Introduction The book Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior is written by Ilhan Kubilay Geēkil

More information

Contents. MA 327/ECO 327 Introduction to Game Theory Fall 2017 Notes. 1 Wednesday, August Friday, August Monday, August 28 6

Contents. MA 327/ECO 327 Introduction to Game Theory Fall 2017 Notes. 1 Wednesday, August Friday, August Monday, August 28 6 MA 327/ECO 327 Introduction to Game Theory Fall 2017 Notes Contents 1 Wednesday, August 23 4 2 Friday, August 25 5 3 Monday, August 28 6 4 Wednesday, August 30 8 5 Friday, September 1 9 6 Wednesday, September

More information

CSCI 699: Topics in Learning and Game Theory Fall 2017 Lecture 3: Intro to Game Theory. Instructor: Shaddin Dughmi

CSCI 699: Topics in Learning and Game Theory Fall 2017 Lecture 3: Intro to Game Theory. Instructor: Shaddin Dughmi CSCI 699: Topics in Learning and Game Theory Fall 217 Lecture 3: Intro to Game Theory Instructor: Shaddin Dughmi Outline 1 Introduction 2 Games of Complete Information 3 Games of Incomplete Information

More information

2. The Extensive Form of a Game

2. The Extensive Form of a Game 2. The Extensive Form of a Game In the extensive form, games are sequential, interactive processes which moves from one position to another in response to the wills of the players or the whims of chance.

More information

1. Simultaneous games All players move at same time. Represent with a game table. We ll stick to 2 players, generally A and B or Row and Col.

1. Simultaneous games All players move at same time. Represent with a game table. We ll stick to 2 players, generally A and B or Row and Col. I. Game Theory: Basic Concepts 1. Simultaneous games All players move at same time. Represent with a game table. We ll stick to 2 players, generally A and B or Row and Col. Representation of utilities/preferences

More information

Game Theory. Department of Electronics EL-766 Spring Hasan Mahmood

Game Theory. Department of Electronics EL-766 Spring Hasan Mahmood Game Theory Department of Electronics EL-766 Spring 2011 Hasan Mahmood Email: hasannj@yahoo.com Course Information Part I: Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to game theory, games with perfect information,

More information

Game Theory Refresher. Muriel Niederle. February 3, A set of players (here for simplicity only 2 players, all generalized to N players).

Game Theory Refresher. Muriel Niederle. February 3, A set of players (here for simplicity only 2 players, all generalized to N players). Game Theory Refresher Muriel Niederle February 3, 2009 1. Definition of a Game We start by rst de ning what a game is. A game consists of: A set of players (here for simplicity only 2 players, all generalized

More information

Game Theory two-person, zero-sum games

Game Theory two-person, zero-sum games GAME THEORY Game Theory Mathematical theory that deals with the general features of competitive situations. Examples: parlor games, military battles, political campaigns, advertising and marketing campaigns,

More information

Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior Chapter 1 and Chapter 2 review

Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior Chapter 1 and Chapter 2 review Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior Chapter 1 and Chapter 2 review Author: Siim Adamson Introduction The book Applied Game Theory And Strategic Behavior is written by Ilhan Kubilay Geēkil and Patrick

More information

INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY

INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY 1 / 45 INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch February 20, 2017: Lecture 1 2 / 45 A game Rules: 1 Players: All of you: https://scienceexperiment.online/beautygame/vote

More information

Resource Allocation and Decision Analysis (ECON 8010) Spring 2014 Foundations of Game Theory

Resource Allocation and Decision Analysis (ECON 8010) Spring 2014 Foundations of Game Theory Resource Allocation and Decision Analysis (ECON 8) Spring 4 Foundations of Game Theory Reading: Game Theory (ECON 8 Coursepak, Page 95) Definitions and Concepts: Game Theory study of decision making settings

More information

Lecture 6: Basics of Game Theory

Lecture 6: Basics of Game Theory 0368.4170: Cryptography and Game Theory Ran Canetti and Alon Rosen Lecture 6: Basics of Game Theory 25 November 2009 Fall 2009 Scribes: D. Teshler Lecture Overview 1. What is a Game? 2. Solution Concepts:

More information

CS510 \ Lecture Ariel Stolerman

CS510 \ Lecture Ariel Stolerman CS510 \ Lecture04 2012-10-15 1 Ariel Stolerman Administration Assignment 2: just a programming assignment. Midterm: posted by next week (5), will cover: o Lectures o Readings A midterm review sheet will

More information

Chapter 15: Game Theory: The Mathematics of Competition Lesson Plan

Chapter 15: Game Theory: The Mathematics of Competition Lesson Plan Chapter 15: Game Theory: The Mathematics of Competition Lesson Plan For All Practical Purposes Two-Person Total-Conflict Games: Pure Strategies Mathematical Literacy in Today s World, 9th ed. Two-Person

More information

37 Game Theory. Bebe b1 b2 b3. a Abe a a A Two-Person Zero-Sum Game

37 Game Theory. Bebe b1 b2 b3. a Abe a a A Two-Person Zero-Sum Game 37 Game Theory Game theory is one of the most interesting topics of discrete mathematics. The principal theorem of game theory is sublime and wonderful. We will merely assume this theorem and use it to

More information

Dynamic Games: Backward Induction and Subgame Perfection

Dynamic Games: Backward Induction and Subgame Perfection Dynamic Games: Backward Induction and Subgame Perfection Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu Jun 22th, 2017 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics)

More information

3 Game Theory II: Sequential-Move and Repeated Games

3 Game Theory II: Sequential-Move and Repeated Games 3 Game Theory II: Sequential-Move and Repeated Games Recognizing that the contributions you make to a shared computer cluster today will be known to other participants tomorrow, you wonder how that affects

More information

International Economics B 2. Basics in noncooperative game theory

International Economics B 2. Basics in noncooperative game theory International Economics B 2 Basics in noncooperative game theory Akihiko Yanase (Graduate School of Economics) October 11, 2016 1 / 34 What is game theory? Basic concepts in noncooperative game theory

More information

What is... Game Theory? By Megan Fava

What is... Game Theory? By Megan Fava ABSTRACT What is... Game Theory? By Megan Fava Game theory is a branch of mathematics used primarily in economics, political science, and psychology. This talk will define what a game is and discuss a

More information

Strategic Bargaining. This is page 1 Printer: Opaq

Strategic Bargaining. This is page 1 Printer: Opaq 16 This is page 1 Printer: Opaq Strategic Bargaining The strength of the framework we have developed so far, be it normal form or extensive form games, is that almost any well structured game can be presented

More information

1\2 L m R M 2, 2 1, 1 0, 0 B 1, 0 0, 0 1, 1

1\2 L m R M 2, 2 1, 1 0, 0 B 1, 0 0, 0 1, 1 Chapter 1 Introduction Game Theory is a misnomer for Multiperson Decision Theory. It develops tools, methods, and language that allow a coherent analysis of the decision-making processes when there are

More information

Opponent Models and Knowledge Symmetry in Game-Tree Search

Opponent Models and Knowledge Symmetry in Game-Tree Search Opponent Models and Knowledge Symmetry in Game-Tree Search Jeroen Donkers Institute for Knowlegde and Agent Technology Universiteit Maastricht, The Netherlands donkers@cs.unimaas.nl Abstract In this paper

More information

Refinements of Sequential Equilibrium

Refinements of Sequential Equilibrium Refinements of Sequential Equilibrium Debraj Ray, November 2006 Sometimes sequential equilibria appear to be supported by implausible beliefs off the equilibrium path. These notes briefly discuss this

More information

Student Name. Student ID

Student Name. Student ID Final Exam CMPT 882: Computational Game Theory Simon Fraser University Spring 2010 Instructor: Oliver Schulte Student Name Student ID Instructions. This exam is worth 30% of your final mark in this course.

More information

Self-interested agents What is Game Theory? Example Matrix Games. Game Theory Intro. Lecture 3. Game Theory Intro Lecture 3, Slide 1

Self-interested agents What is Game Theory? Example Matrix Games. Game Theory Intro. Lecture 3. Game Theory Intro Lecture 3, Slide 1 Game Theory Intro Lecture 3 Game Theory Intro Lecture 3, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Self-interested agents 2 What is Game Theory? 3 Example Matrix Games Game Theory Intro Lecture 3, Slide 2 Self-interested

More information

Introduction to Game Theory I

Introduction to Game Theory I Nicola Dimitri University of Siena (Italy) Rome March-April 2014 Introduction to Game Theory 1/3 Game Theory (GT) is a tool-box useful to understand how rational people choose in situations of Strategic

More information

Leandro Chaves Rêgo. Unawareness in Extensive Form Games. Joint work with: Joseph Halpern (Cornell) Statistics Department, UFPE, Brazil.

Leandro Chaves Rêgo. Unawareness in Extensive Form Games. Joint work with: Joseph Halpern (Cornell) Statistics Department, UFPE, Brazil. Unawareness in Extensive Form Games Leandro Chaves Rêgo Statistics Department, UFPE, Brazil Joint work with: Joseph Halpern (Cornell) January 2014 Motivation Problem: Most work on game theory assumes that:

More information

elements in S. It can tricky counting up the numbers of

elements in S. It can tricky counting up the numbers of STAT-UB.003 Notes for Wednesday, 0.FEB.0. For many problems, we need to do a little counting. We try to construct a sample space S for which the elements are equally likely. Then for any event E, we will

More information

Chapter 30: Game Theory

Chapter 30: Game Theory Chapter 30: Game Theory 30.1: Introduction We have now covered the two extremes perfect competition and monopoly/monopsony. In the first of these all agents are so small (or think that they are so small)

More information

ECON 2100 Principles of Microeconomics (Summer 2016) Game Theory and Oligopoly

ECON 2100 Principles of Microeconomics (Summer 2016) Game Theory and Oligopoly ECON 2100 Principles of Microeconomics (Summer 2016) Game Theory and Oligopoly Relevant readings from the textbook: Mankiw, Ch. 17 Oligopoly Suggested problems from the textbook: Chapter 17 Questions for

More information

Finite games: finite number of players, finite number of possible actions, finite number of moves. Canusegametreetodepicttheextensiveform.

Finite games: finite number of players, finite number of possible actions, finite number of moves. Canusegametreetodepicttheextensiveform. A game is a formal representation of a situation in which individuals interact in a setting of strategic interdependence. Strategic interdependence each individual s utility depends not only on his own

More information

Games. Episode 6 Part III: Dynamics. Baochun Li Professor Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering University of Toronto

Games. Episode 6 Part III: Dynamics. Baochun Li Professor Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering University of Toronto Games Episode 6 Part III: Dynamics Baochun Li Professor Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering University of Toronto Dynamics Motivation for a new chapter 2 Dynamics Motivation for a new chapter

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory (QTM)

Lecture Notes on Game Theory (QTM) Theory of games: Introduction and basic terminology, pure strategy games (including identification of saddle point and value of the game), Principle of dominance, mixed strategy games (only arithmetic

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Review for the Final Exam Dana Nau University of Maryland Nau: Game Theory 1 Basic concepts: 1. Introduction normal form, utilities/payoffs, pure strategies, mixed strategies

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 16 Jun 2015

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 16 Jun 2015 Elements of Game Theory Part I: Foundations, acts and mechanisms. Harris V. Georgiou (MSc, PhD) arxiv:1506.05148v1 [cs.gt] 16 Jun 2015 Department of Informatics and Telecommunications, National & Kapodistrian

More information

Game Theory ( nd term) Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi. Graduate School of Management and Economics Sharif University of Technology.

Game Theory ( nd term) Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi. Graduate School of Management and Economics Sharif University of Technology. Game Theory 44812 (1393-94 2 nd term) Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Graduate School of Management and Economics Sharif University of Technology Spring 2015 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi (GSME) Game Theory Spring 2015

More information

Math 611: Game Theory Notes Chetan Prakash 2012

Math 611: Game Theory Notes Chetan Prakash 2012 Math 611: Game Theory Notes Chetan Prakash 2012 Devised in 1944 by von Neumann and Morgenstern, as a theory of economic (and therefore political) interactions. For: Decisions made in conflict situations.

More information

ECON 301: Game Theory 1. Intermediate Microeconomics II, ECON 301. Game Theory: An Introduction & Some Applications

ECON 301: Game Theory 1. Intermediate Microeconomics II, ECON 301. Game Theory: An Introduction & Some Applications ECON 301: Game Theory 1 Intermediate Microeconomics II, ECON 301 Game Theory: An Introduction & Some Applications You have been introduced briefly regarding how firms within an Oligopoly interacts strategically

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Lecture 2 Lorenzo Rocco Galilean School - Università di Padova March 2017 Rocco (Padova) Game Theory March 2017 1 / 46 Games in Extensive Form The most accurate description

More information

Math 464: Linear Optimization and Game

Math 464: Linear Optimization and Game Math 464: Linear Optimization and Game Haijun Li Department of Mathematics Washington State University Spring 2013 Game Theory Game theory (GT) is a theory of rational behavior of people with nonidentical

More information

Dominant and Dominated Strategies

Dominant and Dominated Strategies Dominant and Dominated Strategies Carlos Hurtado Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign hrtdmrt2@illinois.edu Junel 8th, 2016 C. Hurtado (UIUC - Economics) Game Theory On the

More information

CMU-Q Lecture 20:

CMU-Q Lecture 20: CMU-Q 15-381 Lecture 20: Game Theory I Teacher: Gianni A. Di Caro ICE-CREAM WARS http://youtu.be/jilgxenbk_8 2 GAME THEORY Game theory is the formal study of conflict and cooperation in (rational) multi-agent

More information

Instability of Scoring Heuristic In games with value exchange, the heuristics are very bumpy Make smoothing assumptions search for "quiesence"

Instability of Scoring Heuristic In games with value exchange, the heuristics are very bumpy Make smoothing assumptions search for quiesence More on games Gaming Complications Instability of Scoring Heuristic In games with value exchange, the heuristics are very bumpy Make smoothing assumptions search for "quiesence" The Horizon Effect No matter

More information

Summary Overview of Topics in Econ 30200b: Decision theory: strong and weak domination by randomized strategies, domination theorem, expected utility

Summary Overview of Topics in Econ 30200b: Decision theory: strong and weak domination by randomized strategies, domination theorem, expected utility Summary Overview of Topics in Econ 30200b: Decision theory: strong and weak domination by randomized strategies, domination theorem, expected utility theorem (consistent decisions under uncertainty should

More information

8.F The Possibility of Mistakes: Trembling Hand Perfection

8.F The Possibility of Mistakes: Trembling Hand Perfection February 4, 2015 8.F The Possibility of Mistakes: Trembling Hand Perfection back to games of complete information, for the moment refinement: a set of principles that allow one to select among equilibria.

More information

Section Notes 6. Game Theory. Applied Math 121. Week of March 22, understand the difference between pure and mixed strategies.

Section Notes 6. Game Theory. Applied Math 121. Week of March 22, understand the difference between pure and mixed strategies. Section Notes 6 Game Theory Applied Math 121 Week of March 22, 2010 Goals for the week be comfortable with the elements of game theory. understand the difference between pure and mixed strategies. be able

More information

Weeks 3-4: Intro to Game Theory

Weeks 3-4: Intro to Game Theory Prof. Bryan Caplan bcaplan@gmu.edu http://www.bcaplan.com Econ 82 Weeks 3-4: Intro to Game Theory I. The Hard Case: When Strategy Matters A. You can go surprisingly far with general equilibrium theory,

More information

6. Bargaining. Ryan Oprea. Economics 176. University of California, Santa Barbara. 6. Bargaining. Economics 176. Extensive Form Games

6. Bargaining. Ryan Oprea. Economics 176. University of California, Santa Barbara. 6. Bargaining. Economics 176. Extensive Form Games 6. 6. Ryan Oprea University of California, Santa Barbara 6. Individual choice experiments Test assumptions about Homo Economicus Strategic interaction experiments Test game theory Market experiments Test

More information

ECO 5341 Strategic Behavior Lecture Notes 3

ECO 5341 Strategic Behavior Lecture Notes 3 ECO 5341 Strategic Behavior Lecture Notes 3 Saltuk Ozerturk SMU Spring 2016 (SMU) Lecture Notes 3 Spring 2016 1 / 20 Lecture Outline Review: Dominance and Iterated Elimination of Strictly Dominated Strategies

More information

Topics in Applied Mathematics

Topics in Applied Mathematics Topics in Applied Mathematics Introduction to Game Theory Seung Yeal Ha Department of Mathematical Sciences Seoul National University 1 Purpose of this course Learn the basics of game theory and be ready

More information

GAME THEORY Edition by G. David Garson and Statistical Associates Publishing Page 1

GAME THEORY Edition by G. David Garson and Statistical Associates Publishing Page 1 Copyright @c 2012 by G. David Garson and Statistical Associates Publishing Page 1 @c 2012 by G. David Garson and Statistical Associates Publishing. All rights reserved worldwide in all media. No permission

More information

Behavioral Strategies in Zero-Sum Games in Extensive Form

Behavioral Strategies in Zero-Sum Games in Extensive Form Behavioral Strategies in Zero-Sum Games in Extensive Form Ponssard, J.-P. IIASA Working Paper WP-74-007 974 Ponssard, J.-P. (974) Behavioral Strategies in Zero-Sum Games in Extensive Form. IIASA Working

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Managing with Game Theory Hongying FEI Feihy@i.shu.edu.cn Poker Game ( 2 players) Each player is dealt randomly 3 cards Both of them order their cards as they want Cards at

More information

Advanced Microeconomics (Economics 104) Spring 2011 Strategic games I

Advanced Microeconomics (Economics 104) Spring 2011 Strategic games I Advanced Microeconomics (Economics 104) Spring 2011 Strategic games I Topics The required readings for this part is O chapter 2 and further readings are OR 2.1-2.3. The prerequisites are the Introduction

More information

ECON 282 Final Practice Problems

ECON 282 Final Practice Problems ECON 282 Final Practice Problems S. Lu Multiple Choice Questions Note: The presence of these practice questions does not imply that there will be any multiple choice questions on the final exam. 1. How

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Game Theory I (PR 5) The main ideas

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Game Theory I (PR 5) The main ideas UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A) Game Theory I (PR 5) The main ideas Lectures 5-6 Aug. 29, 2009 Prologue Game theory is about what happens when

More information

Part 2. Cooperative Game Theory

Part 2. Cooperative Game Theory Part 2 Cooperative Game Theory CHAPTER 3 Coalitional games A coalitional game is a model of interacting decision makers that focuses on the behaviour of groups of players. Each group of players is called

More information

Mixed Strategies; Maxmin

Mixed Strategies; Maxmin Mixed Strategies; Maxmin CPSC 532A Lecture 4 January 28, 2008 Mixed Strategies; Maxmin CPSC 532A Lecture 4, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Mixed Strategies 3 Fun Game 4 Maxmin and Minmax Mixed Strategies;

More information

Game theory Computational Models of Cognition

Game theory Computational Models of Cognition Game theory Taxonomy Rational behavior Definitions Common games Nash equilibria Mixed strategies Properties of Nash equilibria What do NE mean? Mutually Assured Destruction 6 rik@cogsci.ucsd.edu Taxonomy

More information

GAME THEORY MODULE 4. After completing this supplement, students will be able to: 1. Understand the principles of zero-sum, two-person games.

GAME THEORY MODULE 4. After completing this supplement, students will be able to: 1. Understand the principles of zero-sum, two-person games. MODULE 4 GAME THEORY LEARNING OBJECTIVES After completing this supplement, students will be able to: 1. Understand the principles of zero-sum, two-person games. 2. Analyze pure strategy games and use dominance

More information

Reading Robert Gibbons, A Primer in Game Theory, Harvester Wheatsheaf 1992.

Reading Robert Gibbons, A Primer in Game Theory, Harvester Wheatsheaf 1992. Reading Robert Gibbons, A Primer in Game Theory, Harvester Wheatsheaf 1992. Additional readings could be assigned from time to time. They are an integral part of the class and you are expected to read

More information

1. Introduction to Game Theory

1. Introduction to Game Theory 1. Introduction to Game Theory What is game theory? Important branch of applied mathematics / economics Eight game theorists have won the Nobel prize, most notably John Nash (subject of Beautiful mind

More information

ESSENTIALS OF GAME THEORY

ESSENTIALS OF GAME THEORY ESSENTIALS OF GAME THEORY 1 CHAPTER 1 Games in Normal Form Game theory studies what happens when self-interested agents interact. What does it mean to say that agents are self-interested? It does not necessarily

More information

Chapter 13. Game Theory

Chapter 13. Game Theory Chapter 13 Game Theory A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes. You can t outrun a bear, scoffs the camper. His friend coolly replies, I don

More information

A Brief Introduction to Game Theory

A Brief Introduction to Game Theory A Brief Introduction to Game Theory Jesse Crawford Department of Mathematics Tarleton State University April 27, 2011 (Tarleton State University) Brief Intro to Game Theory April 27, 2011 1 / 35 Outline

More information

Evolutionary Game Theory and Linguistics

Evolutionary Game Theory and Linguistics Gerhard.Jaeger@uni-bielefeld.de February 21, 2007 University of Tübingen Conceptualization of language evolution prerequisites for evolutionary dynamics replication variation selection Linguemes any piece

More information

Introduction to Algorithms / Algorithms I Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Algorithms and Game Theory Date: 12/4/14

Introduction to Algorithms / Algorithms I Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Algorithms and Game Theory Date: 12/4/14 600.363 Introduction to Algorithms / 600.463 Algorithms I Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Algorithms and Game Theory Date: 12/4/14 25.1 Introduction Today we re going to spend some time discussing game

More information

2. (a) Solve the following two-person zero-sum matrix game.

2. (a) Solve the following two-person zero-sum matrix game. Final Examination Mathematics 167, Game Theory Ferguson Tues June 14, 2005 1 (a) Consider a game of nim with 3 piles of sizes 9, 17 and 21 Is this a P-position or an N-position? If an N-position, what

More information

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications. Kousha Etessami

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications. Kousha Etessami Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications Lecture 17: A first look at Auctions and Mechanism Design: Auctions as Games, Bayesian Games, Vickrey auctions Kousha Etessami Food for thought: sponsored search

More information

February 11, 2015 :1 +0 (1 ) = :2 + 1 (1 ) =3 1. is preferred to R iff

February 11, 2015 :1 +0 (1 ) = :2 + 1 (1 ) =3 1. is preferred to R iff February 11, 2015 Example 60 Here s a problem that was on the 2014 midterm: Determine all weak perfect Bayesian-Nash equilibria of the following game. Let denote the probability that I assigns to being

More information

LECTURE 26: GAME THEORY 1

LECTURE 26: GAME THEORY 1 15-382 COLLECTIVE INTELLIGENCE S18 LECTURE 26: GAME THEORY 1 INSTRUCTOR: GIANNI A. DI CARO ICE-CREAM WARS http://youtu.be/jilgxenbk_8 2 GAME THEORY Game theory is the formal study of conflict and cooperation

More information

Belief-based rational decisions. Sergei Artemov

Belief-based rational decisions. Sergei Artemov Belief-based rational decisions Sergei Artemov September 22, 2009 1 Game Theory John von Neumann was an Hungarian American mathematician who made major contributions to mathematics, quantum mechanics,

More information

Non-Cooperative Game Theory

Non-Cooperative Game Theory Notes on Microeconomic Theory IV 3º - LE-: 008-009 Iñaki Aguirre epartamento de Fundamentos del Análisis Económico I Universidad del País Vasco An introduction to. Introduction.. asic notions.. Extensive

More information

Arpita Biswas. Speaker. PhD Student (Google Fellow) Game Theory Lab, Dept. of CSA, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore

Arpita Biswas. Speaker. PhD Student (Google Fellow) Game Theory Lab, Dept. of CSA, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore Speaker Arpita Biswas PhD Student (Google Fellow) Game Theory Lab, Dept. of CSA, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore Email address: arpita.biswas@live.in OUTLINE Game Theory Basic Concepts and Results

More information

ECO 463. SimultaneousGames

ECO 463. SimultaneousGames ECO 463 SimultaneousGames Provide brief explanations as well as your answers. 1. Two people could benefit by cooperating on a joint project. Each person can either cooperate at a cost of 2 dollars or fink

More information

Backward Induction and Stackelberg Competition

Backward Induction and Stackelberg Competition Backward Induction and Stackelberg Competition Economics 302 - Microeconomic Theory II: Strategic Behavior Shih En Lu Simon Fraser University (with thanks to Anke Kessler) ECON 302 (SFU) Backward Induction

More information

A Survey on Supermodular Games

A Survey on Supermodular Games A Survey on Supermodular Games Ashiqur R. KhudaBukhsh December 27, 2006 Abstract Supermodular games are an interesting class of games that exhibits strategic complementarity. There are several compelling

More information

Multiagent Systems: Intro to Game Theory. CS 486/686: Introduction to Artificial Intelligence

Multiagent Systems: Intro to Game Theory. CS 486/686: Introduction to Artificial Intelligence Multiagent Systems: Intro to Game Theory CS 486/686: Introduction to Artificial Intelligence 1 1 Introduction So far almost everything we have looked at has been in a single-agent setting Today - Multiagent

More information

Simple Decision Heuristics in Perfec Games. The original publication is availabl. Press

Simple Decision Heuristics in Perfec Games. The original publication is availabl. Press JAIST Reposi https://dspace.j Title Simple Decision Heuristics in Perfec Games Author(s)Konno, Naoki; Kijima, Kyoichi Citation Issue Date 2005-11 Type Conference Paper Text version publisher URL Rights

More information

Part I. First Notions

Part I. First Notions Part I First Notions 1 Introduction In their great variety, from contests of global significance such as a championship match or the election of a president down to a coin flip or a show of hands, games

More information